Portfolios for Long-Term Investors* (2024)

Abstract

How should long-term investors form portfolios in our time-varying, multi-factor and friction-filled world? Two conceptual frameworks may help: first, look directly at the stream of payments that a portfolio and payout policy can produce. Second, include a general equilibrium view of the markets’ economic purpose, and the nature of investors’ different preferences, risk-taking ability, and function in that equilibrium. These perspectives can rationalize some of investors’ behaviors, suggest substantial revisions to standard portfolio theory, and help us to apply portfolio theory in a way that is useful in practice.

1. Theory Versus Practice

How should long-term investors form portfolios? How should they evaluate securities, portfolios, and managers? In particular, how should they adapt to the fact that our world features time-varying expected returns, volatilities, correlations, and a plethora of factors, signals, and strategies?

To academics, portfolio theory seems basic to be a solved problem. Merton (1969) gave the answer 50 years ago, building on Markowitz (1952) 70 years ago: split the investment between the market portfolio, the risk-free asset, and factors, that is, portfolios that hedge state variables for intertemporal opportunities.1

The hard work lies in naming the factors, calculating the hedge portfolios, calibrating and solving Merton models, and adapting them to the peculiarities of different investors. This remains a productive and challenging enterprise. Campbell and Viceira (2002) summarize and make large theoretical and practical advances over the early Merton models. But the conceptual framework has not really changed. Even behaviorists view Merton’s advice as the right thing to do, and behaviorally biased agents should simply learn to do Merton better.

Yet Merton’s theory has almost no impact on portfolio practice. With some exceptions, it does not well describe empirically the portfolios that households or institutions hold.2

Institutions—endowments, family offices, insurance companies, pension funds, and the financial management and advice industry—state investment practice in ways we can study and read, beyond just examining the outcome. Their advice and practice is nearly uniform—and has little to do with Merton. Roughly, they start with intense attention to buckets, defined by names rather than betas and correlations: debt and equity; subcategories mostly denoted by industry and other nonbeta characteristics, but now also growth; value and other academic styles; domestic, foreign; “alternatives,” often just an alternative organizational forms which repackage the same securities; real estate, private equity, venture capital, etc. Having decided these buckets down to the last percentage point, these investors allocate each bucket to separate funds or managers, evaluated by rather short-term returns relative to a benchmark, and frequently replaced based on short-term results. As market values change, they quickly rebalance to the benchmark allocations. As many private investors have moved to index funds, many institutions have moved in the opposite direction, preferring illiquid assets that one cannot mark to market and layers of high-fee management. Many such investors sell in downturns. University endowments are a case in point: despite proclamations about being long-term investors that would ride out temporary price fluctuations, many universities sold equities and illiquid “alternatives” in a panic in 2008, during the buying opportunity of a generation.

Payout policy is an integral and overlooked part of portfolio theory. These investors often stick to fixed payout rules in downturns, even as in 2008 when liquidity crises, collateral for derivatives positions, debt roll-over problems, and short-term revenue shortfalls loomed. Universities instituted budget cuts and hiring freezes in 2008 and again in 2020, freezing hiring during the best buy-side markets in a generation. Endowments typically pay out a constant fraction of wealth each period, and do not provide any liability-stream hedging or buffer-stock value (see Gilbert and Hrdlicka, 2015 on endowment payout policies and internal investments).

And this effort produces a pretty discouraging track record by standard evaluation measures, if you do not pick winners expost. For example, Ennis (2020) finds that “Public pension funds underperformed passive investment by approximately 1.0% a year for the 10 years ended June 30, 2018; the shortfall of educational endowments was 1.6% a year.”

The wisdom of high-fee, frequent-trading active management is another striking difference between academic empirical work and practice. A colleague estimates that Stanford pays $800 million a year in fees on a $30 billion endowment. Many wealthy individuals voluntarily pay more than the Sanders–Warren wealth taxes in fees, though an immense academic literature finds no post-fee skill in active management3 (e.g., Fama and French, 2010).

There is no visible mention of state variables or state-variable hedging in any of this process. Multifactor state-variable thinking is also absent from the finance industry. Why do sophisticated quantitative hedge funds, whose reason for being is time-varying expected returns, volatilities, and correlations, multiple priced factors and Merton state variables, whose clients’ horizons are long, and who have sophisticated portfolio optimizers, nonetheless form and evaluate their portfolios on one-period means, variances alphas, and similar return statistics?

Universities employ a large faculty of finance professors, who actively research asset markets. They teach undergraduates and MBAs, so become experts at communicating theory to practitioners, and merging academic and real-world perspectives via case studies and connections to industry. Yet with a few exceptions, university endowments have essentially no connection to all this free high-priced talent. Indeed, most endowments strongly resist input from their finance faculty. I cannot help but suspect that they know what we are going to say and do not want to hear the answers.

Standard fallacies abound. Hedge funds and other institutional investors lever, and try to synthesize a free put option by selling as prices fall. “Carry,” the business of trying to synthesize the writing of put options, litters the finance industry. That is fine, so long as you do not evaluate it by alpha–beta statistics based on short samples and normal distributions. How many times have levered “arbitrageurs” forgotten that they may have to post additional cash collateral if the market gets more irrational before it gets better, or that “we’ll sell on the way down” does not synthesize a free option?

One can read with a bit of hope the spread of “factor investing” or “smart beta” as the provision and purchase of Mertonian hedge portfolios. But which factors should one buy? And just how are style portfolios Mertonian factors, proxies for state-variable risk? Factor-investing funds may promise alpha relative to a factor benchmark, but which factor benchmarks should one buy? What do all these names mean? The style names are mostly meaningless to me, a finance professor. I wonder what the average investor makes of them.

Likewise, the standard list of “investment objectives” that one must declare on opening an account includes a choice between “capital appreciation,” “current income,” “capital preservation,” or “speculation,” in apparent contraction of the theorem that it does not matter whether a return comes from prices or dividends. I have no idea how to translate these concepts to moments of portfolio returns which matter to portfolio theory. Vanguard’s funds seem to follow this conceptual breakdown, offering4 “Diversified equity,” “Dividend Appreciation,” “Dividend Growth,” “Equity Income,” “Growth and Income,” “High Dividend yield,” “U.S. Growth,” “Capital Opportunity,” “Strategic.” What do these mean and who should choose which? BlackRock offers5 1,100 distinct funds. So much for the two-fund theorem. Some names include “Core,” “Income Opportunities,” “Multi-Asset Income,” “Global Allocation,” “Total Return,” “Innovation and Growth,” “Core Moderate Allocation,” “Dynamic High Income,” “Intl Multifactor,” and “Balanced Capital.” What do these mean and how do they map to investor preferences and circ*mstances, or to moments of the return distribution?

When theory is so persistently contrary to practice, at least one of the two must be wrong. One might take the Chicago approach: what is the question to which these practices are the optimal answer? Or one might take the Cambridge approach: deplore how dumb people are not to use the right answer, find “nudges” to induce model-appropriate behavior, or add to the mass of financial regulation to force better allocations.

I think the right answer drinks a bit of both salt and fresh water. Let us figure out why investors are not implementing our theory, and try to make the theory more useful so they are more interested in using it. And let us keep our eyes open to aspects of the world in which their decisions make some sort of sense, and modify our theory to include those more realistic ingredients. Let us also consider agency problems of institutional investors, financial advisers, and other intermediaries which may lead to perverse outcomes.

Cambridge is half right. Normative theory has improved practice. The wide spread of indexing, passive management, and alpha–beta evaluation stemmed from pure theory. It had nothing to do with practice in the 1960s, and was widely derided by practitioners at the time. Value versus growth, factor investing, and behavioral anomaly harvesting sprang from academic research. Chicago is half right too. As I survey seemingly irrational investment practice, I find a lot that actually does make sense as ways to implement Merton ideas, given that asset prices behave much less like random walks than we thought 50 years ago. The world was right to resist.

Merton’s theory is also devilishly hard to implement, which surely helps to account for its disuse in practice. The central problem: what are the expected returns, state variables, betas, or correlations? These are really hard, nay impossible, to measure. What are the partial derivatives of the investor’s value function that guide state-variable investments? That is harder still. And portfolio maximization is very sensitive to inputs.

I offer two basic ideas to make progress on these questions. First, we should focus on the stream of dividends, or more generally payoffs, that an investment can produce, rather than focus on one-period returns. Second, we should take a general equilibrium perspective. An investor should ask: what is the economic function of markets, and what is my role in it? If I want to buy, who is selling and why? Asking these questions can cut through knots of algebra and statistics, and avoid many fallacies. Merton’s portfolio theory corresponds to the ICAPM (Intertemporal Capital Asset Pricing Model) view of market equilibrium. Asset pricing has advanced considerably in offering quite different views of market equilibrium, and the portfolio implications of these new views have not yet been deeply investigated. Putting both hats, I end up glimpsing portfolio theories that are fundamentally different from Merton’s vision, and ways of applying and marketing portfolio analysis that is fundamentally different from the black box so rightly distrusted by real investors.

2. The Payoff Perspective

Payoffs, the stream of payments out of your investment account that you use to support consumption, are the final result of the investment process. We start the statement of any investment problem as a search for the optimal stream of payoffs. We normally then investigate time or state-varying weights of investments in particular assets, and a time or state-varying payout rule that produce the final payoffs. This dynamic programming approach has been enormously productive to actually solve portfolio problems. But we are here to state and understand portfolio problems, not necessarily to get in the weeds of solving them. For that purpose, looking directly at the payoffs has many advantages.

2.1 The Inflation-Indexed Perpetuity

I am inspired by the brilliant Campbell and Viceira (2001) article on long-term bonds. They show that inflation-indexed perpetuity is a riskless asset for a long-run investor. Pay $100, and receive, say, $2 per year, adjusted upward for inflation and downward for deflation (Wachter (2003) generalizes the result).

Their proposition is obvious if you look at the payoffs. An indexed perpetuity gives a perfectly steady stream of real income, which can finance a steady risk-free stream of consumption. It is the risk-free payoff stream. Their proposition is not at all obvious if you look at it in the Merton framework. Perpetuities, like all long-term bonds, look very risky from a one-period perspective. But when bond prices fall, bond expected returns rise. The indexed perpetuity’s expected return happens to rise just enough that the dynamically optimizing consumer can construct a riskless consumption stream. Seeing that fact takes a lot of dynamic programming.

This verity is not at all obvious to the investing world. The idea that indexed perpetuities are the risk-free asset, the foundation point on which investment should start, meets incredulity. How many Master's of Business Administration (MBA) investment classes yet mention this obvious fact, instead of calling money market funds the “riskless asset?” (Mine did, after 2001, but I wonder how many of my ex-students remember the proposition, or would ever say it out loud in their jobs.) In trying to sell my view that the Treasury should issue indexed perpetuities (Cochrane, 2015), I constantly hear “there is no demand” for the product. Indeed, the world is moving away from theory. Perpetuities were common in the early history of government debt, perhaps precisely because they never needed a troublesome roll-over of the principal. The 19th century UK funded an enormous government debt almost entirely with perpetuities, which under the gold standard were essentially indexed. Perpetuities were the go-to asset for aristocrats of 19th century novels to fund a leisurely lifestyle. Perhaps our much better knowledge and understanding of one-period returns, one-period portfolio maximization, and market equilibrium, together with liquid markets, have blinded us to a clearer approach to lifetime investing and long-term borrowing obvious to our ancestors.

Well, let us try to sell some indexed perpetuities. Bring along your infinitely risk-averse spouse who is not a finance professor, and let us set up your retirement portfolio. We will start, of course, with enough indexed perpetuities to keep you and your altruistically linked dynasty going at a minimum standard of living forever.

The next month, the statement comes in. Interest rates have gone up and the value of your investment has plummeted. “Hey, Mr. or Ms. brilliant finance professor,” your spouse intones, “you just lost a third of our retirement savings in your supposed risk-free asset!” Hmm. This is going to be a long conversation, as you delve into state variables, cross-derivatives of the value function, hedges for state-variable risk, dynamic multi-factor models of the term structure of interest rates, and mean-reversion of fixed-income prices.

A much better explanation is, “Honey, look, this investment pays a steady coupon forever that we can live on. That’s the point. We’re not going to buy or sell those bonds, we’re going to live off the coupons. Just tear up the statements, and stop worrying about the portfolio’s mark-to-market value. They’re meaningless for us.”

That bond returns are predictable from their prices or yields is equivalent to the fact that default-free bond cash flows are not predictable from their prices or yields. However, I think the spouse is going to understand the latter better than the former. Rather than explain that a price decline is bad news, but the corresponding rise in expected returns means that we will be OK in the end, let us look at the other side of the identity: when government bond prices decline, that fact has no news whatsoever about the cash flows one will receive.

2.2 Stocks

Now, many risky investments, including stocks, behave a lot like bonds: lower price-dividend or price–earnings ratios largely correspond to higher expected returns, not to lower expected cash-flow growth (Cochrane, 2011 includes a survey). This fact analogously means that stocks are not as risky for long-term investors as one would think looking only at their one-period returns, as low prices are at least somewhat temporary or mean-reverting.

How can we express that fact for an investor? We might try again to say that stocks are natural hedges for their own intertemporal opportunity risk. Low expected returns are bad news, but when that happens prices go up enough to make up for the bad news. Price declines are bad news, but when that happens (are you still listening, honey?) expected returns going forward are better, so we will make up the losses.

Hmm, the spouse is looking dubious again. Do we want to rehash the time you shorted GameStop?

Why do we not say that stocks pay a much steadier stream of dividends than their volatile prices might suggest? The flip side of return predictability is dividend nonpredictability—the two facts are linked by an identity.

But it might be more believable and understandable to say that low prices without a change in dividends do not signal lower dividends ahead, so the strategy of just holding the stocks and eating the dividends is relatively safe, than it is to explain that low price–dividend ratios lead to a just-compensating higher expected return.

Explicitly, using the Campbell–Shiller linearization of return,

rt+1=Δdt+1ρ(dt+1pt+1)+(dtpt)

regression coefficients,

rt+1=br(dtpt)+εt+1r

etc. obey

br=bdρbdp+1.

(2)

Thus for given bdp, bd = 0 is equivalent to br=1ρbdp, which is about what we see in the data. Moreover, since the shocks εd,εdp are essentially uncorrelated, while the shocks εr,εdp are strongly negatively correlated, sampling variation and bias associated with estimation of dividend yield autocorrelation bdp spill over into expected return estimation, but not into expected dividend growth estimation. Including this latter consideration, “dividend yields do not forecast dividend growth” is a more reliable fact than “dividend yields forecast returns” (Cochrane, 2008).

Dividends are not risk free. Stocks are not bonds, even in the long run. But thinking about the dividends directly gives a sense of how risky stock market investing is for a long-term investor. Dividends are obviously driven by overall economic growth, not market gyrations. We all have a sense of how risky that is, and when that risk might kick in. If we are just going to eat the dividends, we do not have to worry about when stock prices might rise or fall relative to dividends. We just have to worry about the economic events that lead dividends to fall.

(By “dividends,” I include all cash payments to investors. True, only about 20% of companies pay conventional dividends, though most of the large ones do so. Other cash payments tend to be lumpy for individual companies, though smooth in the aggregate. Investors and their managers and advisers also can create a payout series by methodically selling, in particular when companies repurchase shares. More on that later.)

2.3 Payoffs Solve Puzzles

Much accounting and finance practice and intuition are built on the idea that prices behave like random walks, that expected returns and variances are constant over time. But much of what people do, which we might have formerly disparaged as irrational, makes sense when risky assets behave somewhat like long-term bonds in this way. So, if looking at the cash flows that result from an initial investment instantly clarifies long-term bond investing, let us pursue the same perspective generally.

Switching to a payoff perspective may change lots of procedures in finance. For example, it is evidently silly to evaluate bond managers by alpha and beta, even relative to a bond index, as if bond returns and alphas are independent over time. Like bonds themselves, any deviation of past bond portfolio return from the index is surely in part a sign of positive returns ahead. A long-term payoff perspective should change bond manager evaluation, and by analogy should pull stock management evaluation away from one-period alphas and betas.

Why do so many institutions, like our endowments, prize assets like private equity, venture capital, and real estate with no clear market values? Well, perhaps they like those assets precisely because the assets are hard to mark to market, easy to just pay out 5% of a made-up value, not to sell in a panic, and not fire the asset manager based on an irrelevant price—or rather a price that is only relevant when combined with the state variable, which accountants and oversight committees are no better at evaluating than our hypothetical spouse. (The chance to cut reported volatility in half with smoothed markings may also be a bit of a reason for this preference. See Stafford, 2017. And while highlighting one, I do not mean to disparage all the other explanations for this preference.)

I used to try to help my mom with her small retirement investments. She would often complain, “Stocks don’t pay much dividends anymore, so how am I to live?” She was of a generation that believed one should never dip into “principal.” I patiently explained that there is no economic difference between dividends and capital gains, between principal and income. It is ok to sell some stock these days. (Taxes, of course, are a different story, and I heartily encouraged her to ignore idiotic advice of big-bank investment advisers to sell stocks held for decades.) But in a world of time-varying expected returns, my mom has a point. Price/dividend yields mean revert, so in the end the long-run “return” of a stock is the stream of dividends divided by the initial price. Living on the dividends is exactly the right strategy for the indexed perpetuity investor, and perhaps not a bad strategy for the long-term equity investor.

When I pointed out that stock prices were high, so she could sell, my mom would reply, “Oh, those are only paper profits,” which sounds like another classic fallacy. I explained the conventional wisdom that the term is meaningless. Prices are prices, and you can sell at those prices! Once again, my mom might have been right. She would be exactly right for a long-term bond portfolio. If an indexed perpetuity price rises, that fact has zero implications for the long-term investor. If bond prices doubled and she sold bonds, she would get a high value, to be sure. But the present value of her consumption path doubled as well, so it would take exactly double the wealth to maintain the same consumption path. Regarding the price rise as “paper profits” guided my mom to the correct Merton decision.

Why do stocks pay dividends? It is a longstanding puzzle. If you go back to the world my mom grew up in, when you had to hold physical shares in a safe deposit box, it makes sense to sell stocks to long-term investors like my mom, that automatically pay out the amount that those investors wish to consume, rather than require investors to trade dynamically in order to construct a consumption/payout stream. In turn, this observation may help us. In principle, dynamic trading can create many “dividend streams” out of an initial set of assets. But corporations and the finance industry have every incentive to create and market the kinds of dividend streams people want. Why do firms pay and smooth dividends? Because my mom liked a steady check! In a sense the definition of “long-term investor” might be one who buys a security for the stream of cash flows, not for a hope of short-term price appreciation.

Shiller (2014) advises people to buy stocks for the dividends. It is good advice. You can read his famous graph, updated there, of volatile stock price on top of very smooth plot of dividends as a plot of the very steady stream of consumption that stocks can support at any date by just consuming the dividends.

Accounting conventions are to some extent to blame for a focus on one-period returns rather than long-term payoffs. Under the early “random walk” view that expected returns are constant and returns are uncorrelated over time, accountants wisely started more and more marking to market. If prices are a random walk, then today’s market value is the best guess of future value, and such marking imposes a lot of discipline on accounting. But marking to market is much more subtle if expected returns vary over time; if prices do in fact suffer temporary declines that are to some extent predictably reversed; if long-run cash flows are more stable than market prices. Such marking would cause less of a problem if one could mark both assets and liabilities to market, as the same discount rate shocks would apply on both sides of the balance sheet. But often one can only mark the assets to market, not the liabilities. More deeply, no accountant can mark to market using state variables that say “yes, we lost a lot on a mark-to-market basis, but these assets will gain back their value in time.” Accountants and bank regulators have resorted to tricks, like putting some assets in “hold to maturity” buckets to avoid marking to market. Resort to tricks reveals the problem.

Insurance companies are not required to mark to market their portfolios unless there is “impairment,” a “permanent” loss of value. They can hold assets at the booked purchase price through maturity, and they do not need to flow into the income statement the fluctuations in their market value other than impairment. They tend to care only about the income their portfolios produce, like my mom, and seldom liquidate appreciated securities.

Houses may be a good example halfway between stocks and bonds. House prices vary a lot. Yet most of us do not market-time housing. Yes, the transactions costs are larger. But the main reason is, we have to live somewhere. The house you want to buy goes up just as much as the house you want to sell. Houses are good hedges for house-price investment-opportunity variation. High house price/rent ratios forecast lower price growth more than higher rent growth. Indeed one of the major benefits of buying a house is that you are protected from rent variation, and can live there as long as you want no matter how high rents go. A house is a housing services perpetuity. (The absence of long-term rental contracts or rent insurance is interesting. One should be able to buy a rent swap, a financial contract that pays, say, the index of rents in a geographic area against a constant flow.)

This observation also says much about wealth inequality. A large amount of the increase in measured wealth inequality is just higher prices for the same payoff streams, as the risk-free rate has declined at least four percentage points, and risk premiums have also compressed. It is then also just “paper wealth” inequality, as long-term consumption inequality does not change at all.

2.4 Payout Theory

Merton’s theory is an integrated theory of dynamic portfolio allocation and consumption or payout strategy. Along with the more famous portfolio advice (1), Merton’s theory says to take wealth out of the portfolio and consume in proportion to the marginal value of wealth,

u(ct)=VW(Wt,yt)

(3)

where u is the utility function, c is consumption, V is the value function, W is the market value of wealth, and yt denotes state variables.

In an i.i.d. world, yt= constant, Merton portfolio theory says to consume in proportion to wealth, which is the market portfolio. That means consumption growth should have a volatility of 20% per year not 1% per year.

People follow this consumption advice even less than they follow the portfolio advice. As evidenced by the low volatility of consumption relative to stock returns, just about everybody ignores “paper profits” in their consumption planning. Estimates of the effect of higher stock values on consumption find small numbers (e.g., Lettau, Ludvigson, and Steindel, 2002). By ignoring the theory’s prediction that consumption should be proportional to the market value of wealth, finance missed the equity premium puzzle for 20 years, merrily fitting portfolios with a risk aversion of two and not wondering why consumption volatility is a tenth of that predicted by the reigning model.

Perhaps people are right, and our usual calibration of the Merton model is wrong. Perhaps changes in stock market values beyond what is reflected in consumption, not just dividends, are transitory, “paper profits” that cannot sustain additional consumption. Perhaps the change in y just offsets the change in W. And perhaps by looking at the payoffs of the investment strategy rather than the market value of wealth, we can see that fact more clearly and communicate it more persuasively.

Perhaps (likely) also the other components of wealth, such as real estate, private business, and human capital, do not vary as much as stocks and bonds, so smooth consumption makes more sense. But real estate values do vary, and why should the true value of private business vary much less than that of public businesses? Moreover, if this is the case, if consumption really does move proportionally to the volatility of true wealth, then standard Merton/Markowitz portfolio advice is severely misapplied by ignoring what must be large components of wealth. I return to outside income and human capital below.

Clearly, we should generalize Campbell and Viceira’s insight, from the riskless asset to the risky portfolio that a risk-tolerant investor will choose. If looking at the stream of coupons and the initial price makes dynamic portfolio theory for the long-term bond investor crystal clear, so looking at the stream of payoffs, the stream of consumption that a portfolio can support, divided by the initial price, should make dynamic Merton theory for the long-term risk-tolerant investor clearer.

2.5 Market Timing and Dynamic Portfolio Management

Campbell and Viceira (2002), by lucidly extending, applying, and expounding the Merton framework, already emphasize that stocks are relatively safe for long-term investors, since stocks are hedge portfolios for their own investment opportunities. Campbell and Viceira also show that long-run investors may wish to market time, investing more when the market is low and less when the market is high. However, the hedge portfolio advice strikes me as more interesting and robust than the market-timing advice. Market timing based on the aggregate dividend yield is a very slow-moving strategy, as the dividend yield takes decades to mean-revert. We do not really know where the average dividend yield is, so whether it is above (buy) or below (sell) average at a point in time is questionable. Real-time evaluations of the market-timing strategy, including the need to estimate the relationship using only past data, are not encouraging (Goyal and Welch, 2003). Formalizing this observation with learning, Bayesian estimation, structural shifts, etc. makes market timing more dubious still. It is possible that we know returns are predictable, and dividend growth is not predictable, but that knowledge is useless for real-time market timing. Real time performance is not a test of the unpredictability hypothesis (Cochrane, 2008).

In contrast, hedge portfolio logic only requires us to believe that the price/dividend ratio does not predict dividend growth. How much of that failure reflects return predictability and how much reflects dividend yield autocorrelation (see Equation (2)) is irrelevant. The hedge portfolio logic only requires us to think dividend yields are stationary, returns are predictable, dividend growth is relatively unpredictable, but it does not require us to know the long-term mean dividend yield, what the predicted return is at a point in time, and how much apparent return predictability stems from downward bias in estimated dividend yield autocorrelation. Finally, we cannot all market time, so it is advice that can only apply to half of the investors, with the other half taking the opposite advice. While one can argue that long-term investors can overweight equity with short-term investors underweighting, market-timing advice applies equally to both. So, in my advice for long-term investors, I deemphasize the market-timing part of the strategy.

Now, the managed-portfolio theorem reminds us that firm dividends really do not matter to the portfolio problem, and there really is no difference between dividends and capital gains. (I abstract from tax issues.) The statistical character of returns and cash flows attaches to characteristics, not to stock name and dividends. One can create a payout by selling stock. A dynamic strategy can synthesize many different cash flows out of portfolios of securities. For example, a fund could market time, or invest in a dynamically managed portfolio of stocks, pay out a 5% payout rate of total value, and that payout becomes the fund’s “dividends.” Of course, as before, firms may already do that. We might consider large corporations and their dividend payout policies already as managed portfolios that provide a dividend tailored in some way to investor’s desires. But funds can potentially improve on that effort, or tailor it to different investors.

The managed portfolio theorem and the essential irrelevance of dividends seem to undermine the payout-focused idea, but I think instead they offer an insight and an advantage. They force us to look at the long-neglected payout policy part of Merton theory. Our endowments spend hundreds of millions on fees for portfolio managers to chase evanescent zero-sum alpha, but then pay out a constant 5% of mark-to-model value, and freeze hiring in recessions. Let us look harder at payouts, and their state-contingency!

Payout policy transfers consumption over time, as portfolio choice transfers consumption across states of nature. If we look at time and state of nature symmetrically, we consider payout policy and portfolio policy together.

There is a tendency to separate portfolio payout from consumption: here is your 5% payout, now you decide when to consume it. But anything not consumed today is put in a bank account or other investment to be consumed later. Put the bank account in the overall portfolio, now we are thinking again about payout policy as part of portfolio policy.

Perhaps this observation reveals another tendency, to think only of certain assets as the “portfolio” and to ignore the others. Universities in 2008 discovered that their borrowing against construction projects exposed them to state-contingent cash flows every bit as much as risky investments in the formal endowment portfolio. The need to roll over municipal debt and maintain a decent rating, or to make good on swap contracts involving such debt, provoked some of the endowment and budget panic of that year. A big piece of my larger advice on applying portfolio theory will be to fold outside assets and liabilities, outside business income to a private investor and professors’ salaries to a university, into the concept of the portfolio. Merton’s advice applies to the whole thing, not one piece of it.

It is inconsistent to advocate state-variable thinking in the portfolio, but to ignore state variables as if returns are i.i.d. in the payout policy (Equation (3)), and just consume in proportion to wealth. (There are special cases in which the marginal value of wealth does not depend on state variables, but they are special, and at least you have to think about it. More later.) For example, suppose interest rates fall, bond prices rise, and our indexed perpetuity investor starts selling bonds to consume a constant fraction of the now higher market value. Sooner or later however, he or she will have to reduce consumption below the pre-planned risk-free value. In this example, the effect of wealth and the state variable, bond yield, exactly offset.

The managed portfolio theorem suggests a sensible dividing line between financial engineering, portfolio selection, and marketing and tailoring a combination of funds to the particular investor. Forming and managing the portfolio, calculating appropriate payouts, hedging state variables, and then cleanly characterizing the available payouts as a stream of “dividends” tailored to the individual might well belong under the hood of expert management, and worth a fee. Management companies now sell target date funds, annuities, and defined benefit pensions, each of which functions in this way. The suggestion is just to offer a much richer set of carefully tailored payouts.

Under the hood, the manager may well wish to take a dynamic programming, state-variable approach. A bond fund with a more complex portfolio than an indexed perpetuity, or a more interesting set of payouts such as annuities, should definitely use yields as state variables, and model how changes in yields are likely to affect returns and payouts going forward. Likewise, a value fund, recognizing that book/market ratios forecast returns over time as well as (or more strongly than) the cross-section, should include the time variation in book/market ratios as a state variable, and use that to forecast returns and cash flows, in order to determine its payout policy. And educated customers need to understand and believe in what the fund is doing. Modeling has to be part of the business—figuring out if prices decline, just how much expected returns have risen, and how much expected dividends have fallen, and figuring out what will happen if those forecasts are off. Still, I think it remains useful to communicate, and for the final investor to contemplate and evaluate the portfolio plus payout product, by focusing on the character of the stream of payoffs it produces rather than the dynamic strategy under the hood.

Options provide another good analogy. Black, Scholes, and Merton showed how one can replicate an option by dynamic trading in stocks and bonds. Suppose an investor is worried about stock market risk—“I’m willing to take some risk to generate higher average returns, but I absolutely cannot take a fall in value more than 20%.” Obviously, the right investment strategy is a stock index plus a protective put option. But it might be more efficient to synthesize that put through dynamic trading. Now how do we explain this advice to the investor? The protective put—the final payoff—is clear and simple. The dynamic trading strategy is much harder to explain. Even if the portfolio manager executes the strategy by dynamic trading, or by options trading, it is much easier to explain and to choose the protective put by explaining the final payoff.

2.6 Evaluation

Currently, many funds characterize their performance for investors by alpha and beta relative to a market index such as the S&P500. Alpha and beta relative to the S&P500 is only interesting if your portfolio, including your outside income and liability streams, consists only of the S&P500. A marginal investment only improves mean–variance performance if it has alpha relative to your portfolio. Alphas and betas are only interesting if your objective is one-period mean-variance optimization. Alphas and betas are only interesting if you are doing alpha–beta risk management and evaluating a whole portfolio on that basis. Our investors do not hold that portfolio and they do bucket-based not beta-based risk management.

Alphas and betas are even less interesting in a dynamic context, for long-term investors. In classic asset pricing theory, betas derive from the correlation of cash-flow shocks. But now we know that prices move on discount rate news, so betas are also driven by common discount rate shocks. Then, S&P500 alphas and betas are only interesting if you care about the discount-rate betas, but the discount rates are not a state variable to you.

Standard alphas and betas do not include state variables. For example, a value fund with low recent alpha currently does not estimate how much a low state variable today means higher returns in the future.

Alpha and beta relative to a factor index such as a value index is a little more interesting. But only if that the deviation from the index, α+ϵ is uncorrelated over time and unforecastable, which it is likely not. Like bonds, if a fund’s stocks fall more than the index, they may well be better bargains. But the most important question for the long-term investor is which of the dozens of factor indices to buy. Alphas relative to those indices are icing on the cake. First, let us figure out how to bake the cake.

To be concrete, let us take the hard job of a value fund manager in late 2020. It is a lot like our beleaguered finance professor trying to explain the indexed perpetuity to an incredulous spouse. If value stocks fall, and their dividends, earnings, etc. do not fall, value stocks are likely an even better deal than before. (Time-series value is stronger than cross-sectional value. Book/market variation over time predicts subsequent returns of the same portfolio more strongly than book/market variation across portfolios predicts returns. See Cochrane, 2011, table AIII.) The same is true of funds that operate on convergence trades or long-term arbitrage opportunities. But going to client meetings, explaining that you have just lost a ton of mark-to-market money, but the state variables just keep getting better and better, so if anything the client should invest more, is awfully hard! Selling momentum is a lot easier. “Paper losses” do not have quite that much ring in a modern client meeting. And not irrationally so. Any ambiguity or learning about the process puts weight on realized returns. But the same learning and statistical doubt would not believe that indexed perpetuity bond returns mean-revert as well.

If the conversation were about long-run payouts, about the price paid for a dividend stream, the whole business might be a lot easier. It is still not easy—unlike a bond, one needs to model the long-run payouts. But it seems a more productive way to frame the conversation.

2.7 Risk Management

Looking harder at the risks and risk-absorbing capacity of the liability stream or planned consumption (and philanthropy) stream is a vital and overlooked component of the portfolio process. Liability streams are not fixed, and often a choice rather than a fixed set of payments. If an institution is not going to buy indexed perpetuities, then the supported income stream is risky, and will have to be cut back at times and states of nature dictated by the portfolio and payout strategy. What are those times and states of nature? How costly will it be to cut back in those events? These questions need to be asked.

A university that invests in risky assets should be sure that the payment streams supported by the risky payouts can absorb the risk. Tenured professor salaries are, in the current institutional framework, hard to cut in bad times. Adapting to risk by cutting back investment in new faculty may not be the smartest way to absorb risk. Flashy new centers, showy initiatives, larger staffs, nonrevenue teaching, outreach efforts, and related activities are easier to scale up in good times and to scale back in bad times. Whatever one thinks of such activities, universities do a lot of them. If those activities can bear risk, they are better suited for funding from the risky payoff streams of an endowment invested in risky assets. Indeed, the confluence of risk bearing capacity and risky endowment strategies may explain some of the modern university’s dramatic shift in the direction of such activities. A sovereign wealth fund might think likewise about which streams of payments can bear risk, and which cannot. Funding entitlements with a risky portfolio seems more dangerous than funding science or infrastructure, for example. Many wealthy individuals invest, on the margin, to fund philanthropic ventures. Their preferences about such funding may well be quite risk tolerant. That fact leads to a strong positive beta in donation flow, another state-contingent stream that university and nonprofit endowments need to think more about in their risk management. On the other hand, a defined benefit pension fund, an individual with a lot of debt, for example, mortgages on houses that he or she really would be pained to sell, needs to find other consumption streams that can bear risk or reduce the risk in the portfolio.

2.8 Analytical Approaches

This remains vision, and it is all easier said than done. In Cochrane (2014), I extended Campbell and Viceira (2001) to risky assets. If the indexed perpetuity is the riskless asset, then the consumption claim, that pays one unit of aggregate consumption, must be the risky claim and held by the average investor. People must mix their portfolios between these two claims, with more risk averse people taking more of the indexed perpetuity, and vice versa. And all of this holds with an arbitrarily dynamic and multifactor view of the world.

Dynamic portfolio theory and asset pricing are really about the question, how does one extend simple one-period results to multiple periods? Conceptually, my paper suggests we extend one-period asset pricing to multiple periods by looking at streams of payoffs, rather than make the one-period terminal utility more complex, as the value function of a dynamic program. Treat date and state symmetrically. Write intertemporal dynamic portfolio choice as a choice of the final payoff or consumption streams,

max{c(st)}t=0stβtπ(st)u[c(st)]

where st denote states of nature. In a complete market, we can write the constraint

W=t=0stβtπ(st)mt(st)c(st).

The optimal payoff c^(st) is given simply by

u[c^(st)]=λm(st).

This condition fully describes the optimal payoff over time just as it is does across states of nature, despite arbitrary dynamics, state variables, multiple factors, etc. This result is well known (Cochrane, 2014 includes a literature review).

However, we do not live in a complete market. The state variables for time-varying mean returns are not traded. The challenge is to do the same sort of analysis in an incomplete market. To that end, I simply write the dynamic Merton problem as static Markowitz portfolio theory, treating date and state symmetrically. Start with a set of basis payoffs x(st), which can be expanded by dynamic trading and payout strategies. Then the constraint is

c(st)=iwixi(st),iwipi=W.

I made the problem look even closer to the one-period problem by defining “long run” moments that sum over date and state symmetrically,

E˜(x)(1β)t=0stβtπ(st)x(st).

(4)

Likewise we can define long-run variances, covariances, betas, etc.

Though the environment is arbitrarily dynamic, all the standard one-period characterizations obtain. We can define a long-run mean/long-run variance frontier, price assets from long-run betas, etc. But it all has a much different meaning. The long-run mean, variance, and covariances are of dividend streams divided by initial price. We look at asset prices, driven by the long-run covariance of dividend streams with the marginal utility stream, in place of one-period returns. Hedging outside income streams is easy too, discussed below.

That long-horizon perspective can make a big difference in how we proceed. Consider the problem of betas, central to risk management and portfolio formation. Another great puzzle is how little we know about betas. In continuous-time diffusion theory, 10 s of millisecond data is enough to measure betas with nearly infinite precision. In fact, betas are hard to measure and unstable over time. Much of the reason, I think, is that most betas are discount-rate betas, not cash-flow betas. (Or they are sentiment betas, if you are in a behavioral mood.) Discount-rate betas measure how one price moves with another price, while the dividend streams do not move at all. Most of this variation is irrelevant for our long-term use. The payoff view focuses on long-run cash-flow betas, defined by a long-run covariance as in Equation (4). They are fundamentally different objects.

More generally, applied Merton portfolio theory is foundering. Campbell and Viceira, and the related literature, have done a good job of adapting Merton theory to what we now understand about the evolution of the market, and perhaps a few styles like value and growth, over time. But applying Merton portfolio theory for long-term investors to our current nuanced multifactor understanding of the cross section remains terra incognita. Perhaps this payoff-focused view will let us convincingly describe cross-sectional portfolio theory, overcoming the instability of Σ1μ.

Alas, after (in my view) an inspiring introduction, my paper foundered a bit. The linear marginal utility or linear–quadratic approximation that one needs to generate two-fund separation in an incomplete market is a difficult fit to power utility and lognormal long-term returns. So the statement that investors who differ by risk aversion split their payoffs linearly between the indexed perpetuity and the aggregate consumption claim is not a great global approximation to the power-lognormal environment. For example, when investors have power utility, the complete-market sharing rule is

ciγi=λcaγa

where i and a are individual and aggregate. Log consumption is a linear function of log aggregate consumption, but the relationship between levels is nonlinear.

So, my linear two-fund payoff theorem may survive as useful conceptual benchmark. But you can see in this sharing rule that it may not be a good approximation far from the endpoints, indexed perpetuity and market dividend claim. I leave a better formal analysis an invitation for smarter people than I am to follow if, as I hope, I have persuaded you it is a good idea either for calculating or for marketing consumption–portfolio advice and especially outside-income hedging where we do not have mark-to-market values. (Cochrane, 2007 and Cochrane, 2013 include many seemingly obvious paths that do not work. If you get inspired, see here for a list of things not to do.)

One may object that it takes a long time to evaluate whether the stream of dividends accruing to an investment is good or not, or to calculate the long-run mean, variance, and covariance of long-run cash flows. But it takes a lot of time to evaluate average returns too. The tyranny of σ/T ensures that measuring and evaluating payouts will have to include some modeling, understanding how state variables like bond and dividend yield forecast future returns or cash flows. And prices never really go away from the portfolio problem for finite horizons and data. You can have a great stream for a while if you plunder the terminal value.

The long-run perspective also changes what is important. Translating returns to prices can make a big difference if return differences are persistent. For example, at a price/dividend ratio of 50, P/D=1/(rg) gives us rg=2%. From that a 20 bp change in return equals a 10% change in price. Many people do not get excited about a 20 bp change in average return (Especially those paying 2%+ 20% fees!). But increasing lifetime consumption by 10% is something to write home about. On the other hand, things that loom large to the highly levered, high-speed trading and transient anomaly end of finance fade from interest, as they make little difference to the price of long-term cash flows.

At a simpler level, dividends are what matters for long-run returns. The price–dividend ratio mean reverts, so all of the eventual return comes from dividends divided by initial price, not from capital gains. All unexpected long-run return comes from unexpected dividend growth. We can see these facts directly by rearranging the Campbell and Shiller (1988) decomposition, in logs, to express the long-run return in terms of long-run dividends and the initial price,

j=1ρj1rt+j=j=1ρj1Δdt+j(ptdt).

Even more simply, we can just write the definition of return,

Rt+1=Pt+1+Dt+1Pt=Pt+1/Dt+1Pt/DtDt+1Dt+Dt+1Pt

In the long run, the price dividend ratio reverts to its mean, P/D, so, loosely (!) a very long-run return becomes

Rt+1=P/DPt/DtDt+1Dt+Dt+1Pt=(1+PD)Dt+1Pt=RDt+1DtDtPt.

Dividend growth is what matters to long-run returns. Fama and French (2002) use this idea to measure the equity premium. The postwar period saw a large increase in the price/dividend ratio, which will not go on forever. They argue that the lower average dividend growth is a better measure of the equity premium. One may also argue that even the postwar dividend growth was unexpected, representing decades of stronger economic growth than the world had ever seen or was expected in the aftermath of WWII.

2.9 From One to Many Periods—Payoffs or Returns

In sum, the challenge of contemporary portfolio theory is to move from a one-period understanding to a multiperiod, dynamic view. This generalization is easy if the world is i.i.d.—just play the one period over and over. But our world is not i.i.d., so one-period tools do not work. Merton extends the one-period world to a dynamic world by dynamic programming, adding state variables that capture changing conditional distributions to the terminal utility, which is the value function of the dynamic program. Now, dynamic programming often does capture common intuition and behavior and offers a digestible way to operationalize dynamic maximization. When someone says “I can’t afford to go out to that fancy dinner,” they are trading marginal value of consumption u(ct) against marginal utility of wealth VW(Wt,yt). Keeping a rough sense of the marginal value of wealth around is a much better heuristic for decision making than trying to trade off date and state-contingent consumption—“I don’t want to go out to a fancy dinner tonight because I might want to buy a better class of RV when I retire in 40 years.” Dynamic programming does capture the process of much decision-making as well as the outcome. But in the portfolio case, we do not know really what the state variables are, the derivatives of the value function do not have such an easy interpretation, and they depend on the environment as well as preferences. Viewing the problem as a selection among cash-flow streams may be an easier way, at least to implement and market portfolio theory, if not directly to compute portfolios and recommended consumption.

3. A General Equilibrium Approach

The second conceptual aid I want to offer is that researchers, investors, and advisers should routinely state a view of the economic function of financial markets, their place in markets, what activity or risk bearing generates a reward, and what justifies doing something different from everybody else. In our language, portfolio theory and application should describe a general equilibrium, and how investors are heterogeneous.

Why you may ask? When you buy tomatoes at the grocery store, you do not need to think about general equilibrium. If tomatoes are expensive, buy less of them. Who cares if they are expensive because of a frost in the tomato farms or because of a behavioral bubble in the tomato futures market? Consult your preferences, look at the price, and buy accordingly. This is exactly the Merton approach in financial markets. Whether expected returns are low because of a behavioral bubble or because everyone else is less risk averse or because of a savings glut in China makes absolutely no difference to your portfolio calculation. Whether markets are efficient, behavioral, or institutional makes no difference.

But asset markets are different from grocery stores in one crucial respect: we don’t know the prices. We do not know the expected returns and betas that appear in Merton portfolio theory and take the role of prices in grocery-shopping microeconomics. Expected returns take decades to learn, thanks to σ/T, and then they change. The factor structure of returns is devilishly hard to measure, and also varies over time. (Again, I suspect that is because so much of it represents discount-rate betas. I hope that long-run cash-flow betas are more stable and sensible. But nothing in finance turns out the way you think before you look.) Alternatively, we know asset prices, but we do not know what we get for that price. It is as if the store says tomatoes are $5.00, but you have to take them home and wait 20 years to find out how many tomatoes you actually got for your $5.00.

Now if you cannot see the prices and have to do a lot of statistics to guess what they are, thinking about general equilibrium can help to make a shopping decision. If you know that tomatoes grow on farms, that they are ripe in August, and these facts drive the seasonal behavior of tomato prices, then you know buying a lot of tomatoes in August when the posted price is low is likely to be a good idea.

General equilibrium thinking starts with a deep, powerful, and frequently overlooked theorem:

  • The average investor must hold the market portfolioI.

The first implication: if you are not identifiably different than average, then you should hold the market portfolio. You should not even rebalance. If stock prices go up, from 60/40 of total assets, to 80/20, and you rebalance to 60/40, someone else has to overweight equities. Rebalancing is a zero-sum market-timing strategy.

The average-investor theorem is powerful, because portfolio theory is hard. You have to estimate or otherwise understand time-varying means and covariances of asset returns and state variables, alphas, and betas. Then you have to make a difficult computation, and do a lot of massaging to keep it from blowing up. But if you know that you are no different than the average—or if you do not really know you are different and how—you are done, you know the answer. Off to the total market portfolio with you.

Indeed, if you have ever tried to do a portfolio optimization, even at the level of MBA class problem set, you know how essentially impossible it is. The optimization is sensitive to small variation in mean returns and covariance matrix. If you want the maximization to come up with anything like the market portfolio, you have to reverse-engineer that result by forcing expected returns to equal betas times the market return. Even slight deviations cause huge changes in portfolio weights. Starting with the market portfolio, and then isolating respects in which you are different from average is a promising way to construct a portfolio.

A consequence:

  • • Any deviation from the market portfolio is a financial zero-sum game.

For everyone who gains, or earns an alpha, someone else must lose. I add the “financial” qualifier because the whole point is to find deviations that make sense for everybody in marginal utility. But that only happens if we are different from each other in some important way.

• Portfolio theory must be all about heterogeneity.

So how are you different than average? Everyone thinks they are smarter than average, or less behavioral, or better informed. Half are, by definition, wrong about that.

Well, just hire a smart person. Sorry, the finance profession has free entry of charlatans at all levels. (Berk and van Binsbergen, 2020 offer an equilibrium model of “charlatans.”) You have to be better than average about picking managers. Half of the people are wrong about that too. Maybe you think you deserve alpha because your social connections are better than average. You golf with this brilliant options trader named Bernie. Half the people are wrong about that too.

A good test of a portfolio theory, a portfolio maximization program, or portfolio adviser, is that there must be a question to which the answer is to do nothing: hold the market portfolio without rebalancing. This is a vital placebo test. If the program or adviser says “you should buy value and short growth,” then ask, “and who are you telling to short value and buy growth?” If the answer is “nobody, this is a great deal for any investor,” at a minimum the portfolio view is not fleshed out. If it is honest, then it is useless for almost all investors—the vast majority of people are solving some other portfolio problem, which gives the “buy growth” answer. Are you sure you are not one of them? Otherwise, we are back in the town where all the children are smarter than average. At best, if it truly is good advice for any investor, then when investors wise up and take the advice, the phenomenon will disappear. Are you sure you are first in line? Are you sure you are not talking to someone who is offering the portfolio advice that leads to the negative alpha that others will exploit? In sum, any style or factor advice such as “buy value” is clearly more reliable if we know the portfolio question whose answer is “buy growth,” and the question whose answer is “hold the market,” and we can check that these are not our questions.

The average investor theorem reassures you that by holding the market index you can at least protect yourself from being below average! The dismal literature on active management, constantly reminding us that there is essentially no reliable after-fee performance better than indexing, is a powerful incentive to remember the average investor theorem. Thinking in market microstructure terms, avoid being the “liquidity” trader who the “informed” traders and “market makers” pick off.

In sum, the average investor theorem suggests a few related tests for portfolio formation:

  • The placebo test.

  • The look-in-the-mirror test.

  • The dinner with lions/look around the table test.

The placebo test is, again, the test that there must be a well-defined question to which the portfolio advice spits out, hold the market.

If you are buying, others must be selling, and they have a reason to do so. Maybe they are more behavioral than you, or less informed, or dumber. Maybe they have some exposure to state variables you do not have. Maybe they have a “liquidity need.” But first, look in the mirror. Are you sure you are not the one who should be selling?

When having dinner with lions, make sure you are at the table not on the menu. Someone is. When sitting down to play poker, find the mark. Make sure it is not you.

If you want to deviate from the market portfolio, ask first, “What are the risks of this security, why are others unwilling to hold that risk, and why am I the right person to do so?”

General equilibrium, or at least some economics, should be useful also in guiding our thinking about asset price and return dynamics. I asserted that stocks are a lot like bonds, that expected returns vary over time, that higher valuation ratios correspond to lower expected returns, and, equivalently, that higher valuation ratios do not correspond to higher expected dividend or cash-flow growth. But statistical estimates of time-series predictability and the states of nature when it goes wrong are imprecise. Faith in state-variable hedging, marking values to market-based on higher expected future returns or a rosy estimate of a dividend stream might be excusably weak. If one states a general equilibrium view of the causes of discount-rate variation and expected dividend growth variation, that view give one more confidence in state variables. For example, in the fall of 2008, one could clearly see many investors dumping securities, as they got nearer to balance sheet capacity or default boundaries. The smell of time-varying risk aversion was in the air. Such thinking gives an investor who does not have such constraints, or reason to become more risk averse, confidence that this is a time of higher time-varying expected return. And such thinking invites a look in the mirror to make sure our investor really does have more risk-bearing capacity than the average.

Moreover, being clear about whether the fundamental source of time-varying returns comes from time-varying investor behavior, time-varying technological investment opportunities, or time-varying wedges driven by financial frictions, intermediary constraints, etc, can help an investor think through the right strategy at a moment in history. Portfolio theory is not usually stated in general equilibrium terms, but it would be much more helpful if it were to do so.

3.1 Portfolio Theory and Equilibrium Asset Pricing

The last 50 years have seen immense progress in asset pricing, both theory and empirical work. Much of work this still awaits integration with portfolio theory. Simply throwing every anomaly in the soup and sending it off to a Merton portfolio optimizer is obviously a bad idea.

Why has so much asset pricing theory and empirical work since the ICAPM not translated into parallel portfolio theory and application? In part, I think because we simply have not asked them to do so. We have mostly used new theories, including new preferences, technology specifications, and the recent discoveries about market frictions, to ask the opposite question—what asset price variation do we reverse-engineer so the portfolio theory answer is just to hold the market portfolio?

That is already interesting. It reminds us that perhaps we too are not the Merton investor, and have the same novel preferences or face the same opportunities as everyone else, so what look like delicious trading opportunities are in fact prices that should guide us to hold the market portfolio just like everyone else.

But asset pricing per se does not give any portfolio advice other than that the average investor should hold the market, no matter how zany the asset prices are. Here, I think the brilliant insight of Lucas (1978) may have taken us too far. Before Lucas, we thought of asset prices with the traditional general equilibrium framework: write down supply and demand (portfolio) curves, then intersect them to solve for asset prices. The CAPM and mean–variance theory came hand in hand; the ICAPM and Merton theory came hand in hand. Lucas taught us to skip portfolio theory altogether, and just read asset prices from first-order conditions in equilibrium—when the investor holds the market portfolio. That was a tremendous shortcut for asset pricing, but it put portfolio theory a bit in the rear-view mirror.

So, let us survey quickly some of the new asset pricing theories, or views of the function of markets, buttressed by facts. Let us think about how to introduce relevant and interesting concepts of heterogeneity—how people or their circ*mstances differ, motivating different investment strategies, different payoff streams. Let us think about how to complete the equilibrium models too, as many theories do not describe a full or heterogeneous set of agents, or supply conditions. And then we can speculate how the new understanding of asset pricing might change portfolio theory, focusing here on long-run investors.

3.2 The Classic View and Updates

I start with the classic view, completing Merton portfolio theory with CAPM or ICAPM general equilibrium, to get this way of thinking going. Here, the purpose of financial markets is to intermediate between investors who manage portfolios of wealth, with time-separable expected utility and no job or outside income, and firms that need to issue securities to finance investment. In the classic i.i.d. case, investors differ by risk aversion. They hold more or less of the market portfolio and risk-free asset accordingly.

The general equilibrium underpinnings of the CAPM and ICAPM are actually not always clear. The most straightforward way to think of the CAPM or ICAPM in general equilibrium is to view stocks as linear technologies, promising a fixed stochastic rate of return independent of investment size, that is, linear technologies. Market equilibrium changes the composition of the market portfolio by changing the scale of its constituent firms. Market equilibrium does not change the price or rates of return of individual securities. Time-varying return moments stem from time-varying technological opportunities. The CAPM can also be derived by assuming that asset payoffs are fixed, and equilibrium determines initial prices and therefore expected returns. Reality lies in between, and includes market frictions.

This classic marriage of CAPM/ICAPM and Markowitz/Merton portfolio advice is already useful for practice. If investors are to answer “What’s my risk aversion?” it is awfully hard to come up with a number. Various surveys and questionnaires to elicit such a number are only fodder for behavioral finance in their inconsistency. Like rats in a maze, we are as-if maximizers not self-aware calculating automatons. But if investors have only to answer, “Are you more risk averse than the average investor?” perhaps we can make progress. Of course, beware surveys. Not everyone can be less risk averse than average either, though many may strike that pose. And people who state low risk aversion in good times often change their minds in the tough after-the-big-loss meetings with their asset managers. But that fact only suggests time-varying risk aversion which we will get to later. Still, one way to make sense of the questionnaires that all investment advisers make us fill out, which I made fun of above, is that they are trying to elicit this sort of relative rather than absolute variation in preferences.

Moreover, as before, actual portfolio maximization using average return and covariance matrix estimates is devilishly unstable. By posing the question in this general equilibrium form, we reduce the problem to a simple two-fund question.

However, the CAPM and ICAPM fail as empirically relevant general equilibrium models. If everyone were Merton (separable utility, no outside income, and common information) investors, it is awfully hard to have a market that produces the kind of multifactor time-varying opportunities we see. Why are all these opportunities there? Why did not everyone else take them? Whose portfolio demands are causing these apparent opportunities to emerge in the first place? If we cannot answer these questions, then we should really wonder whether the advice is right.

Substantial progress has been made applying and extending the basic Merton framework, recognizing heterogeneity beyond risk aversion, and some of this progress has made its way to practice. I will again let Campbell and Viceira (2002) be the exemplar and summary of a huge literature. They largely implement Merton-style theory, though with recursive utility, in a statistical environment that captures broad newly understood dynamic features of asset returns and avoiding the nettlesome Σ1μ step.

In the classic i.i.d. world, portfolio allocation is independent of horizon, and academics disparaged conventional wisdom to the contrary. Hedging demand and calibrated return predictability from valuation ratios rescues another piece of practical-world advice. Long-term investors who can “wait out market downturns” should invest in stocks, just as their risk-averse long-term investor should invest in indexed perpetuities. Stocks are like bonds, a good hedge for their own expected-return risk. Campbell and Viceira quantify this effect.

But people and institutions may now differ in terms of investment horizon, not just risk aversion. A one-period investor does not care about state variables. State variables and hedging demand are only important for investors with longer horizons. And horizon now gives an additional dimension of heterogeneity to violate the average-investor theorem.

The investment industry has responded to academic advice and horizon heterogeneity on top of risk-aversion heterogeneity by implementing target-date funds that invest more in equity when people are younger, and then gradually move to an all-bond investment when people retire. However, in the meantime academics have become less sure that this is the right advice, or why it is the right advice. Yes, intertemporal hedging suggests some of this behavior. But why should people in very long retirements not wish any equity? Even with short horizons they are classic Merton investors who should take some risk for its return. Most people with any money to invest are also planning to make bequests or charitable contributions, effectively giving them a much longer horizon. The bequest can absorb risk.

Much of the target-date strategy is also motivated by the idea that wage income is bond-like, so people with wage income should tilt more to stocks, and people who retire should replace the bond-like wage with bond-like investments. But it is no longer clear that wage income is a bond-like investment (more below).

Target-date funds’ aggressive rebalancing in response to variation in stock prices also runs afoul of the average investor theorem—we cannot all rebalance. According to Parker, Schoar, and Sun (2020) such rebalancing drives supply shocks of the institutional-finance sort which affect equity prices. We end up holding the market portfolio one way or another. Target-date funds might at least target fractions of market capitalization that vary with age, rather than rigid portfolio weights that vary with age, to avoid such rebalancing.

3.3 Outside Income Risk, a Giant Insurance Market

Consider a different vision of markets and heterogeneity: investors also differ by outside income risk or liability streams. The economic function of markets is a giant insurance mechanism for spreading risk around.

Most individual investors, especially weighted by wealth and thus market impact, own substantial non-marketed businesses or real estate. Our universities invest to fund stochastic liability streams such as the difference between tuition, gifts, and government subsidies less our and burgeoning staff salaries. Pension funds and insurance companies invest to support liability streams. And human capital, the stream of wage and other earned income is perhaps the largest of all sources of nonmarketed income.

Before chasing alpha, investors should hedge these outside income streams. That hedging demand moves the typical investor away from the market portfolio. It can move prices and expected returns away from the i.i.d. CAPM, and thus generate the multifactor and time-varying premiums that we see in asset returns. The few lucky pure wealth investors then can earn superior returns by selling the hedge portfolios, writing insurance to the rest. People who are less exposed to a common factor in outside income streams sell insurance to those who are positively exposed.

Now, just how do you hedge an outside income stream? The advice to do it has been given many times. People and institutions do not do much of it, which remains a puzzle. Simply avoiding one’s company or industry in a portfolio is not that hard for investors large enough to have separately managed accounts. Yet beyond such obvious name-based strategies, even calculating the appropriate hedge portfolio for many income streams is difficult. In particular, labor income for many people attaches to their human capital, and not the industry in which that capital is currently employed, so just shorting one’s company or industry may not be effective. Finance professors might want to short the finance industry which drives our salaries, not higher education which also employs anthropologists. Academic attempts to calculate such hedge portfolios have an awfully hard time doing it. We need to think a lot harder about how to do it. (The literature review in Cochrane, 2014 contains many valiant efforts to calculate portfolios with outside income in incomplete markets.)

Here too, I think this goal is more easily thought of and perhaps implemented in terms of streams of cash flows rather than the properties of one-period returns.

The central problem in hedging an income stream is marking it to market. Most asset return variation is, again, due to discount-rate betas not cash-flow betas. You do not see any change in the cash flows yet all of a sudden you are supposed to cut their value in half, and look for securities that also fall by half at the same time?

Suppose we had only the dividend stream of the S&P500 in hand, and could not observe prices. None of us could come within a factor of two of the S&P500 market price, and less so of changes in that price. So if your labor income stream, or your private business’ profit stream were exactly equal to the S&P500 dividend stream, and you set out to mark to model, then search for securities correlated with the resulting monthly, quarterly, or annual returns, it would be very unlikely that you would figure out to hedge these streams by reducing your allocation to the S&P500 index. In evaluating the portfolio strategy or a manager who implements it, there is little chance that you and your accountants would see this as a successful hedge a year later when the market rises 50% and you missed it. Yet if you just look at the S&P500 dividends, ignoring prices, the answer would jumped out at you. So let us look at the stream of dividends, or the cash flows from managed strategies, and find those streams that best match the labor income stream directly, ignoring one-period returns.

This method might produce a pretty thorough revision of the standard picture. The income streams of well-paid people or business owners are likely a lot like S&P500 dividends, and if anything more cyclical, and prone to disaster shocks in bad times, and correlated with the dividend streams of their firms or industries.

Where did we get the idea that wages are a bond-like investment? Well, because we are not very good at marking wages to market with the nebulous but highly time-varying discount rates that apply to marketed dividend streams. If you marked S&P500 dividends to market using a constant discount rate, they would look pretty bond-like too.

(Ideas to better complete markets by selling insurance for idiosyncratic wage, house price, rent, and business income complement this vision. But here let us think just about portfolio theory in existing markets, or at best how intermediaries in such an effort could hedge the aggregate risks in their portfolios.)

The long-run mean–variance concept makes this idea transparent. Let the investor have an outside income stream h. Then the optimal portfolio x comes from solving

maxE˜[u(c)]s.t.W=E˜(mx);c=h+x.

In a complete market the optimal portfolio is

u(x^+h)=λm

which we can solve for

x^=u1(λm)h.

Sell off the hedge portfolio for outside income, then invest as before. But the purchased portfolio x^ contains both components.

Cochrane (2014) takes up this idea in incomplete markets. You can easily construct a hedge portfolio for income h by running a long-run regression of the stream h onto the set of asset payoffs. The hedge portfolio is the fitted value of that regression. I also show how market prices are affected when a mass of investors has such outside income and adds up to a hedging demand. Again this analysis looks just like easy one-period portfolio theory, but the symbols c, x, etc. all have date and state subscripts so we are solving the dynamic stochastic portfolio problem.

This is a coherent and plausible general equilibrium view. It explains why opportunities might be there for the lonely mean–variance investor: he or she is selling insurance to a mass of others whose incomes vary with a state variable, such as recessions, with a component orthogonal to the dividend stream of the market index. Fama and French (1996) offer this view as one cohesive explanation of the value effect and factor.

Given this view, however, it is a puzzle that finance theory and industry are so exclusively devoted to the small number of investors who have no outside streams, can profit by selling insurance to the others, and have not yet done so. If this is the view of the world, the majority of investors should want to buy insurance of one sort or another. At a minimum, for every investor we help to guide to value because his or her outside income is not correlated with value payoff streams, there should be another investor we help to short value, despite its attractive return (dividends/initial price), because that loss of return is a small premium paid for valuable insurance. The absence of the latter ought to be unsettling. But maybe that is only a failure of marketing, or a historical relic of the era before mass investing and institutional investing.

Moreover, in this view of the world, it is a puzzle that portfolio theory and practice does not focus on the unpriced factors, and that the pages of our journals are so completely devoted to finding priced factors and positive alphas. In this view, the most interesting portfolios are not the priced ones useful to the last mean–variance investor, but portfolios in which there is a lot of heterogeneity in risk exposure, and strong hedgeability, high correlations of the portfolio stream with the income streams of a large mass of potential customers. R2 to large factors of investor outside income, not S&P500 alpha, should be the measure of interest and dominant statistic for getting papers published. Whether such portfolios have S&P500 alpha is irrelevant. Indeed zero-alpha portfolios are better as they offer actuarially fair insurance.

Industry portfolios are a prime example. These portfolios are well priced by standard factor models, and not even badly priced by the CAPM. Helping people to short their own industry should offer valuable utility improvement, worth a nice fee. It should be the cornerstone of every 401(k) retirement plan, though it has no alpha to the few lucky investors who do not have a job or business.

To date, this general equilibrium view of the world has not fared that well: historically, value did not do that badly in recessions, justifying it as a risk factor for recession-related falls in labor or business income. However, the disastrous results of value funds in the last two recessions may help to restore the theory, if not the fortunes of value funds in a world where marketing is still driven by short-term alphas, the allure of being smarter than the others rather than shouldering state-variable risk. And this empirical evaluation is still based on one-period returns, not on cash flows. If we look at value patterns in dividends—which is exactly the general pitch for value stocks; buy dividends at low prices—do we see that stream of dividends more closely correlated to the streams of incomes of many investors who shun value stocks? The idea has a long way to go.

Much of value investing consists of deliberately not looking under the hood. When investors look at value stock names, companies that have fallen, companies with no news or glamor, companies on the edge of failure that statistically come back more frequently than not, companies just offering steady streams of dividends at low prices, those investors often run away. Now, perhaps by forcing a quantitative selection over behavioral bias, value strategies allow people to buy what they would not buy if they looked under the hood, and allow all investors to buy stocks that others irrationally shun. But perhaps investors who shun value stocks when they see the names are seeing in those names some commonality with their own fortunes. But if it is wise not to look under the hood at company names, perhaps not looking under the hood at high-frequency returns, at least without really understanding state variables and cross-derivatives of the value function, is also valuable discipline.

We move on, but I first emphasize the general point, more general than my two frameworks (payoff streams and general equilibrium). Most income is not marketed, and most investors have outside income or outside liability streams. These streams are risky and heterogeneous. It is likely that many such streams are hedgeable in markets. The second most important thing a portfolio strategy should do is to hedge that risk. (The first is not to pay taxes needlessly.) Such hedging does not depend being smarter than average, knowing something others do not know, harvesting alphas, etc. Unlike alpha, it is a positive-sum game, and advice one can offer to every investor with a straight face. Yet hedging outside streams is painfully absent in professional asset management. If anything many individual and institutional portfolios take on more of the risk they are already exposed to. At a minimum, 401(k) options or defined benefit plans can avoid their own company stock, and then their own industry. There are many heartbreaking contrary stories, for example, airline pilots who had all their 401(k) in company stock and the company goes bankrupt. Universities with medical centers should not hold hospital stocks in their endowment portfolio. Some universities have already taken this step.

There is a great desire in the portfolio industry to sell individually tailored portfolios, and charge a fee for that tailoring service. There is some hedging, in the form of rate of return swaps or option positions for extremely wealthy individuals with concentrated ownership of companies they started. But though portfolio management advertising emphasizes how firms tailor portfolios to individual circ*mstances, just what that means, what circ*mstances they can recognize and meet with useful advice, remains murky at best.6 And standard investment advice one receives at typical portfolio managers is already strikingly inefficient. Typical managers advocate frequent rebalancing, churn the portfolio, do not avoid short-term capital gains, charge fees to allocate portfolios to dozens of different high fee funds, and do not routinely sets up a portfolio to avoid taking any capital gains until death, instead borrowing against shares or hedging exposures instead. We are a long way from setting up outside income hedging.

The heart of portfolio theory with a general equilibrium perspective is to identify relevant heterogeneity. But when I read investment companies’ required survey questions about my investment goals—“capital preservation,” “growth,” “income,” and the larger list I made fun of above—I, with some background in finance, have no idea what they are talking about. Perhaps academic portfolio theory can help to make this a serious enterprise—and one that can charge a nice fee in equilibrium.

The average personal investor sits on a nontraded, highly leveraged, illiquid asset chock full of idiosyncratic risk—the owner-occupied home. That government policy heavily encourages such a disastrous investment, under the fallacy that homes “build wealth” (better than stocks), is obviously partly to blame. People in many other countries rent houses, and the first thing a consumer financial protection effort should do is to discourage such investment. (Getting 401(k) out of company stock might be the second.) Given the policy, however, it is puzzling that intermediaries have not routinely helped people to hedge house-price risks. Shiller (1993) argues for better financial along with many other market improvements to help insure individual and macro risks. However, housing futures and similar contracts designed around risk sharing have not been a big success, which remains a worthy puzzle. Below I suggest a view that exchanges are built to facilitate information trading or speculation, rather than useful risk sharing. Still, intermediaries and advisers could be doing a lot more than they do with existing markets and with portfolio advice.

3.4 Cash-flow betas, Factors, and State Variables

The long-run, cash-flow perspective has also begun to change our picture of asset pricing. So far this research has not led to much explicit portfolio theory, but it is clearly suggestive of new directions for portfolios. This effort nicely coincides with an effort to understand the value-growth premium in terms of the different character of their cash flows.

Following Campbell and Vuolteenaho (2004), the separation of beta into cash-flow betas and discount rate betas, has become more widespread. Sensibly they find that cash-flow news is more persistent and cash flow or “bad” beta generates a larger premium. Discount rate-induced falls in prices are transitory, less important to long-term investors, and thus carry a smaller premium.

Cho and Polk (2020) find that a long-run CAPM focusing on cash flows describes the cross-section of prices much better than the cross-section of returns, and an interaction of book to market and quality provides a strong second factor.

Campbell, Polk, and Vuolteenaho (2009) find that cash flows of growth stocks are sensitive to market discount rate changes, while cash flows of value stocks are driven by market cash-flow changes. Thus, growth stocks are good hedges against expected market equity returns. When the market expected return declines, that is bad state-variable news. Market prices go up, and future growth-stock cash flows go up. So the market is a good hedge for its own state-variable risk, and growth stocks are an especially good hedge for that risk. This finding suggests that growth stocks may not be such bad investments for long-horizon investors even without outside income or other sources of heterogeneity. And therefore, when we add heterogeneity driven by horizon, long-term investors may want to hold growth stocks while short-term investors hold value stocks.

Growth stocks have growing, and thus delayed cash flows. Value stocks have steadier or declining cash flows with shorter duration. A big literature accounts for the value-growth premium in this way, see for example Gormsen and Lazarus (2019) and cited literature. Again, premiums for near-term or delayed cash flows suggest a portfolio theory in which horizons should also matter for the cross section.

Betermier, Calvet, and Sodini (2017) find that individuals do obey many of the suggestions we have sniffed out so far for long-run portfolios, an unusual example contradicting my negative assessment of the theory’s empirical performance. In a large panel of Swedish residents, they find that “households progressively shift from growth to value as they become older and their balance sheets improve. Furthermore, investors with high human capital and high exposure to macroeconomic risk tilt their portfolios away from value,” which is “consistent with the portfolio implications of risk-based theories of the value premium.”

3.5 Macro-finance, New Preferences, State Variables, and Rare Disasters

Merton portfolio theory is based on power utility. But if investors were all like this, we would be unlikely to see the asset market factors and dynamics that we see. (It is possible that return dynamics come entirely from changing technological opportunities, but the bulk of modeling finds their source in preferences or market structure.) In the 50 years since Merton, lots of different preferences have been brought to finance to account for those factors and dynamics. Recursive utility (Epstein and Zin, 1989), habits (Campbell and Cochrane, 1999, and precursors cited there), ambiguity aversion (Hansen and Sargent, 2001 is the first of a long series), aggregation theory bringing in cross-sectional risk to asset prices (Constantinides and Duffie, 1996), or cross-sectional preference variation (Garleanu and Panageas, 2015), and economy-wide or individual rare disasters (Reitz, 1988; Barro, 2006; Schmidt, 2016) are just a few. The specification of technology has gotten more interesting than endowments or linear production technologies that look like rates of return. Gomes, Kogan, and Zhang (2003) is an early influential example of a large literature. Ferson (2019) has an excellent treatment of current multifactor models.

It seems that fundamentally changing preferences or technology should change portfolio theory. Yet these advances have not yet made a large inroad to Merton portfolio theory. For example, Campbell and Viceira (2002) include recursive utility, yet this change per se has not yet substantially changed Merton’s basic advice. Most of Campbell and Viceira’s novelty comes from calibrating the input parameters to Merton calculations, finding ways to easily calculate the portfolios, and making clear sense of the results.

With log utility—both risk aversion and intertemporal elasticity of substitution equal to one—the optimal investment is myopic, ignoring state variables, and the payout policy gives consumption proportional to wealth. A risk aversion substantially above one while keeping the intertemporal elasticity near one generates Mertonian portfolio advice while keeping the constant payout rule. Since institutions pay out a constant fraction, that may seem a realistic parameter configuration.

It does not seem that institutions are doing much Mertonian state-variable hedging. They do not describe portfolio allocation in such terms. They report 1-year returns. They do not report state variables, or expected returns or cash flows going forward based on state variables. If we take their current behavior as optimal, they look pretty myopic, that is, risk aversion near one. But such low-risk aversion implies a counterfactually large equity allocation. Perhaps considering their large explicit debt—tax-free debt issued against construction—implicit debt—tenured faculty and hard-to-fire staff salaries—and the high beta of donations, perhaps they are more exposed overall than it seems. Still, this view still has them holding the market portfolio, which they manifestly do not do.

As before, wealthy investors do not consume a fixed fraction of wealth, but seem largely to ignore discount-rate-related “paper profits.” Finally, even a desire to consume a fixed fraction of mark-to-market wealth does not make sense of university decisions to ignore outside income streams. In the pandemic years 2020–21, most universities continued to pay a fixed amount out of endowment, while adapting to revenue losses with budget cuts and eliminating investment, especially in new faculty. So overall, recursive utility, while a potential advance, is not by itself the answer.

Mostly, I think, the insights of macro-finance have not made inroads in portfolio theory because we simply have not asked them to do so. We have mostly used these preferences and technologies to ask the opposite, asset-pricing, equilibrium question: what asset price variation do we reverse-engineer so the portfolio theory answer is just to hold the market portfolio?

Again, that observation is already interesting. It reminds us that perhaps we too are not the lone Merton investor living in a multifactor dynamic world, and maybe we have the same novel preferences or face the same opportunities as everyone else, so what look like delicious trading opportunities are in fact prices that should guide us to hold the market portfolio just like everyone else.

Habits, for example, are a parable for time-varying risk aversion. They generate a market in which prices have a strong temporary component and expected returns vary over time. The representative agent sees a delicious low-price opportunity, but just before jumping on it, notices that his or her risk aversion and precautionary saving motive has risen so much that, despite the opportunity, he or she will just end up sitting on the market after all.

To be useful for portfolio theory, then, we need to include interesting and empirically plausible dimensions of heterogeneity in formal equilibrium models and informal equilibrium thinking. Does my risk aversion vary over time less than yours? Why? Habits look a lot like debt boundaries. Are you less indebted than average? Even if true habits, in the model John Campbell and I wrote down, people arguably differ. Most academics seem to live well below their means. Others are the highly leveraged high-beta wealthy, Queens of Verisailles who buy multiple highly mortgaged enormous houses. Thinking in ambiguity-aversion terms, if my “worst-case” scenarios are different from yours, we will want different portfolios. If my idiosyncratic risk exposure varies with aggregates differently from yours, we have a reason to trade.

The behavior of our endowments and university budgets in 2008 and 2020 are worth thinking about in this context. Why did they sell in a panic in 2008? Why were there budget cuts and hiring freezes then and in 2020, each university missing a golden chance to snap up talent the others are ignoring?

In 2008, universities discovered that they had liability streams and leverage. Their rise in risk aversion looks a lot like time-varying risk aversion induced by getting closer to a boundary, with tenured faculty salaries and municipal bonds serving as the reference point that induces a spike in risk aversion. One adviser to an endowment explained patiently to me that yes, December 2008 was the buying opportunity of a lifetime, but that if stocks did continue to slide, it would destroy the institution. The endowment could not take the risk, so was selling anyway. Surely, however, knowing this fact, they should have set up portfolios differently, at least for the next crisis?

That the same budget crisis happened only 12 years later is more puzzling. OK, in March 2020, one could see a second financial crisis on the horizon. But by June that risk was clearly over. A Powell version of Draghi’s “do whatever it takes” did what it took. Well, university cash flows were clearly disrupted by the pandemic. For many schools, there remains a good question just how long they will remain financially viable. That is not an issue for large-endowment schools, but they still faced disruptions to their cash-flow streams. Stanford, for example,7 saw a greater need for financial aid, to support PhD students in a disastrous job market, and a drop in revenue. Still, this disruption is clearly temporary. $35 billion in endowment should not lead to a strong sensitivity of investment (new faculty) to temporary cash flows! So, it seems our universities again experienced a big increase in risk aversion and precautionary savings desires. But why? And how can we better structure portfolio and payout rules to meet the possibility of such changes in the future?

(Campbell and Sigalov (2020) address some of these puzzles of endowment behavior, in particular why endowments seem to react to lower interest rates by taking on more risk. They add to the power utility investor a constraint that the investor consumes out of endowment, and may only consume the expected return times the endowment, so that the endowment is expected to maintain its value. When interest rates decline, such an investor would like to consume more now and less later. Facing the spending constraint, the investor chooses a riskier and higher expected return portfolio, consuming more now and a more volatile stream later.)

Rare disasters offer a different and deep challenge to portfolio theory as well as asset pricing. Both the economy and financial markets display a non-normal distribution of shocks, with occasional crises and then quiet good times. Rare disasters, of quantities or of marginal utility, mean, however, that the covariances with marginal utility cov(xt,u(ct)) that drive both one-period risk premiums and long-run payoff covariances and asset prices may have nothing to do with the covariances we measure in normal times. All that matters is, how does the asset do in the crash state? Is the rare disaster in outside cash flow hedged on this, the only really important day? Not only do everyday discount rate betas not matter, everyday cash-flow betas do not matter either! Robust control or ambiguity averse preferences give much the same flavor, isolating only a few states of nature that drive everything.

That view is logically consistent, but discouraging if true. Quantitative portfolio management and risk analysis are hard enough when monthly betas matter. If measurable betas are irrelevant, the problem becomes even more speculative. If rare disasters are important, to institutional survival if nothing else, then most of what standard portfolio theory does is irrelevant. Evaluating annual returns and hiring and firing managers on the basis of standard alpha and beta measurement is irrelevant. On the other hand, if rare disasters are important, then thinking through how markets work, what one’s place is in them, and how they are likely to behave in a rare disaster state—the general equilibrium + heterogeneity approach—is even more important relative to statistical analysis and portfolio maximization based on such analysis.

Disasters raise a principle that perhaps I should have stated at the beginning:

  • portfolio formation begins with risk management.

Think about the worst states. What are the states of the world in which you, or your institution are in deep trouble? How does the portfolio and payout policy hedge those states? Only then start getting greedy about paying a low price.

The Fed’s stress tests for banks are an interesting example of this approach, mixing some robust control and general equilibrium thinking in risk management. Bank’s risk should be well captured by value-at-risk analysis which computes standard betas to sophisticated statistical models of the evolution of asset returns and their correlations. That is the analog of our standard portfolio theory. Yet the Fed evidently does not trust this calculation, and instead poses some simple scenarios that do not even have probabilities attached to them. Perhaps the question to which stress tests are an answer is one more portfolio managers should ask. (That stress tests did not think to ask “what happens in a pandemic,” is however a caution on this approach.)

Heterogeneity is exploding in macroeconomics and finance, in part due to technical improvements in our ability to solve models with heterogeneity, and in part due to realizing that heterogeneity can matter for aggregates. Portfolio theory is all about heterogeneity, of course. In early models like Constantinides and Duffie (1996), people face uninsurable idiosyncratic risks, uncorrelated with any asset returns. The presence of background risk can affect overall willingness to hold stocks, but does not shift which kinds of stocks people hold. But since marginal utility is non-linear and the cross-sectional variance of individual risks can vary with aggregates, their model can deliver rich patterns of asset pricing and asset holding. Their paper reminds us that the representative investor preferences can include measures of heterogeneity of the individuals. Garleanu and Panageas (2015) show that when people differ by risk aversion, the market develops time-varying expected returns. Less risk averse people have larger equity positions, so in downturns, the average investor becomes more risk averse. That has a direct implication for time-varying portfolios. (see Panageas, 2020 for a recent, eloquent, and comprehensive survey of heterogeneity in asset pricing.) Recent models with more kinds of heterogeneity interacted with portfolio constraints offer portfolio advice directly. See Garleanu and Panageas (2019) for a survey.

Campbell (2018) lays many foundations for the heterogeneous agent approach to portfolio theory. The entire part III of the book is devoted to “heterogenous investors.” Campbell considers heterogeneity based on labor income, limited participation, undiversification, and exposure to uninsurable individual risk. And he treats heterogeneity in beliefs, which underlies “information” trading, perhaps the most important divergence from passive investment there is, summarizing a huge but still young literature.

3.6 Trading and Liquidity

Perhaps, however, the central function of asset markets is neither saving and investment, nor a giant insurance market, but to facilitate trading on information. If so, then long-term investors are to some extent a side-show. But their investment strategies should take account of this fundamental purpose of markets.

Trading and volume are, I think, the great unsolved finance question of our time. Why is there so much volume? The standard models we have thought about so far do not produce a hundredth of the observed trading volume.

Of course, we sort of know the answer: trading volume is high because people trade on information—or what they think is information. But standard theory runs smack into the no-trade theorem, part of the average investor theorem, and its dinner with lions lemma. If someone wants to sell you a security, and you feel like buying, he or she knows something you do not know. We cannot all be more informed than average. If uninformed traders refuse to budge off the market portfolio, as they should, then efforts to trade on information simply move prices to reflect that information with no volume.

Yes, we have an immense theory of information trading to try break that logic. We write models with a signal about a terminating dividend. But most price movement is discount-rate movement, that is disconnected from dividends. Are there really signals about discount-rate movements? Trading models require exogenous “liquidity traders” or overconfident agents to surmount the no-trade theorem. They are the suckers who do worse than average. Who are they? Are you sure you are not one of them?

Our exchanges are built and exist in order to facilitate information trading, or speculation, if you prefer. That is their most obvious function. Share issues, retirement saving, even outside-income hedging, do not need exchanges and instant trading. Exchanges were obviously not built to accommodate those demands. Those demands could all be handled in retail markets, like houses, cars, and insurance. Is the existence of exchanges, going back half a millennium, really just testament to human folly? Would exchanges not exist if we all processed information better? I think not. But that means we really do not have a complete theory of what trading is about.

The standard trading models clearly can be improved. Why does it take a hundred trades for information to make its way into the market, or really for traders to merge their actual information and to develop a consensus view? (e.g., Santosh, 2014). The world is filled with thousands of confusing signals, not the tight structure of our models. Information is something like internet rumors that snowball, merge, and refine to success, or die out, each tweet a trade, not a card game with exactly fifty-two cards and we all know which ones. Perhaps the next generation will find a mathematical structure to model this process.

I digress a bit, because this is I think vital direction for asset pricing in the future. But we are here to think about portfolio theory, using what we know today. In advance of such deeper understanding, how does the evident fact that markets are built to facilitate a lot of high frequency “information” trading affect our long-term investor?

I will stick to long-run investors who do not want to participate in information trading, or even to shade their portfolios based on hunches that this or that security or industry is the wave of the future, investors who simply do not wish to be the short end of the average investor theorem. You might immediately say “index,” but that is not necessarily true. If trading demands push prices around, then an uninformed investor can profit by underweighting, or even shorting, assets that trading has pushed up in value, just as the unexposed investor can profit from by selling insurance if hedging demands are pushing prices around.

In the first blush of efficient markets, we thought we could separate information trading from portfolio theory, on an empirical understanding that trading activity had no effect on the level of prices. Since then, however, we have more and more evidence that trading activity moves the level of prices.

I start with one simple phenomenon: highly traded securities have higher prices, lower average returns, due to the convenience yield that their shares give to information traders. The conclusion is natural: long-term investors should avoid such assets.

At a most basic level, money pays less than bonds (or at least it used to do so). Well, money turns over more, and is used for trading. The implication for long-term investors is obvious: hold as little money as possible and do your investing in bonds. Do not stuff your mattress with money.

We now recognize sizable liquidity and trading-related spreads in government bonds. On-the-run versus off-the-run spreads exist. Longstaff (2004) is particularly clean, comparing Treasury yields with Refcorp bond yields, which had explicit Treasury credit guarantees, and finds 10–15% price discounts. Krishnamurthy and Vissing-Jorgensen (2012) document a sizeable liquidity premium in all US Treasury debt. That premium declines when the supply is larger, just as a “money demand” might do, and is traceable to the value of Treasury debt in financial transactions and the immense daily turnover of Treasuries.

As I write, the Moody’s AAA yield is 2.6% (December 2020). These are bonds of more than 20 years maturity, so let us compare them to the 30-year constant-maturity Treasury rate of 1.7%. A measly 0.9 percentage point yield spread does not seem to be much to get excited about. But look at the flows. For each $100 invested, you can get a steady $2.60 annual coupon in AAA rather than $1.70 in Treasurys. AAA bonds are not a 0.9 percentage point better return. They are a 53% better return; a 53% better cash flow for the same price! The long-term investor should buy AAA bonds not on-the-run Treasuries. (Yes, this is a bit of an overstatement as there is presumably more default risk in AAA. A better calculation would cover that risk with Credit Default Swaps. But the probability of default times recovery is certainly not this large in the index of AAA bonds.)

What if the AAA bonds lose value, if liquidity spreads spike as in 2008? The long-term investor should not care. If you ask the question, look hard in the mirror. You are not a long-term investor.

If a security has a high value due to its liquidity or transactions value, and you do not care about liquidity or transactions value, do not buy it. This is a consistent general equilibrium view. Another class of investors, evidently, does care about the liquidity and transactions value of Treasuries, and is willing to hold them despite low returns. Again, look hard in the mirror—our endowments said they were the long-run investor who does not panic in a crash, holds for the long-term, harvests liquidity premiums. And then tried to sell in a panic. It turns out they were the ones who should have been overpaying for liquidity all along!

An enormous amount is written about “safe asset demands,” “safe asset shortage,” etc. Much of this has a behavioral, or yet-to-be-worked-out general equilibrium basis, as it is not clear just why there should be so much demand for nominally default-free assets. Still, on these stories too, if it passes the look in the mirror test, the long-term investor should not buy safe assets that other investors are driving up in value.

I advanced this view of asset prices in Cochrane (2003). In stocks also, we see high prices and low expected returns where turnover is high, share supply is low, and a large amount of “information” trading (speculation if you wish) is going on. The pattern is particularly clear when it rises to the point of apparent arbitrage opportunities. I looked at the 3Com/Palm arbitrage brilliantly analyzed by Lamont and Thaler (2003). A small number of Palm shares had been carved out, and 3Com shareholders would receive the rest in 6 months. The direct Palm shares traded at a huge price premium over the Palm shares embedded in 3Com. The overpriced end of the arbitrage (Palm) had much higher turnover, higher bid/ask spreads, strong short sales constraint, all indications of a strong demand to trade on Palm “information.” Who are the behavioral dummies who hold Palm rather than the Cheaper 3Com? Nobody—the average Palm holding was 2 weeks. Palm overpricing is a small cost of doing business if you think you have information about Palm. The overpricing is a lower cost than bid–ask spreads if you are going to hold Palm for 2 weeks. Even to short Palm you have to own the shares for a little while, so a symmetric divergence of opinion drives share prices up.

If you are a long-run investor, who wants to hold Palm for the dividends, the strategy is simple: buy 3 Com and wait 6 months for the distribution of Palm shares. Or, actually, stay away from the whole NASDAQ tech sector.

The pattern is widespread, suggesting to me that a great deal of security value may lie in the value of shares for information trading—and that there are broad categories of stocks that long-term investors should avoid, substantially shading their portfolio away from the market-weighted index.

Price and trading volumes correlated strongly through the first Internet boom and bust, with NYSE, Nasdaq, and Nasdaq tech each having larger booms and busts in price and volume together. And when the trading boom vanished, so did the extra value. (If there is a reverse causality story, that would be just as interesting, but I cannot think of one.)

The correlation between price and volume extends across individual securities. There is a strong (Fama MacBeth t-statistic over 7) cross-sectional correlation between volume and market-to-book ratio. The “growth” stocks are where all the trading action is, where all the information is, where all the fun is. And, as we know, growth is where the prices are highest and returns are lowest.

A similar and strong correlation of market value with volume occurred in the radio, phonograph, washing machine, and automobile boom and bust of the 1920s. High valuations coincided with high trading volumes, and the market decline correlates beautifully with a decline in volume. House price (price/rent ratios) are high when trading volume is high and vice versa.

The small growth overpricing anomaly is one of the largest around, and strangely ignored. In Fama and French (1996), table 1, for example, the small growth portfolio has the distinction of a−45bp/month three-factor alpha, with a 4.19 t-statistic, twice as large as any other portfolio. Why? Well it is suggestive that the small growth portfolio is where all the information trading action is. For example, Davis (2001) examines fund performance by manager style. In the usual story of rampant underperformance, Davis finds one ray of hope for active management, a positive 17-bp/month alpha for the deepest growth funds. Active managers, who trade on information, are able to beat the index of the most overpriced stocks around. (It is curious that this anomaly is so overlooked. Do we just care about positive alphas?)

The implication of this view for a long-term investor is clear: do not hold stocks with high prices relative to book, dividends, earnings, etc. when those high prices are correlated with high trading volume, low share supply, and lots of buzz in social media, lots of information traders. To be clear, we are not (just) worrying about being on the wrong side of asymmetric information here. We are worrying about buying stocks whose price has been driven up by the combined demands of traders, for whom the shares are an entry ticket to betting on information. If you are investing to get long-term relatively risk-free dividends at a low price today, stay out of Tesla, Gamestop, and bitcoin.

The resulting portfolio is likely to differ substantially from the market index. The value-weighted market index includes all these high-flying stocks, and in larger proportions precisely because of their inflated prices.

Avoiding stocks with high information trading is again something professional management can help with, for a fee. For who owns the overpriced shares? Who owns the short end of an arbitrage? Who owns Palm rather than 3Com? Who owns the more expensive of two identical classes of payoff-identical HSBC shares? (Maymin, 2011). Who owns Royal Dutch rather than Shell when the latter is more expensive? (Rosenthal and Young, 1990). Who owns shares in companies that win the all-time prize for negative alpha—companies that are having a battle between short-sellers and management? (See the delightful Lamont, 2012). Who owns Gamestop and Tesla? Well, not just the information traders. Index holders and quantitative factor-beta funds hold all of these, and the more overpriced, the more they hold. If like me you have some part of a low-cost total market index, you and me are on the wrong end of these investments. If you buy one of everything, you will not notice an arbitrage opportunity, two claims to the same dividend stream selling at different prices!

I emphasized one story for these anomalies, the convenience yield for information-based trading. There are many anomalies, many “overpriced” securities, and many more stories to explain them. Lamont and Thaler chalk up the 3Com/Palm arbitrage opportunity to (p. 231) investors who are “irrational, woefully uninformed, endowed with strange preferences, or for some other reason willing to hold over-priced assets.” Such an interpretation has the same implications for long-term investors. However, it invites a different look-in-the-mirror test. We are all human, and everyone thinks they are less behavioral than the others. I prefer the information-trading guide because it is more restricted. You have to look for high trading volume as well as “overpriced” securities. It also gives a general equilibrium story and a description of heterogeneity in which everyone is almost rational, up to the small problem of the no trade theorem which I think we may solve someday. Lamont and Thaler’s story only applies to those investors who are less behavioral than average. And who does not think they are in that class?

A liquidity premium is a different object than a convenience yield. Palm shares had huge turnover despite large bid/ask spreads, reflecting a large demand for informed trading. Treasury bonds have huge turnover because of low bid/ask spread, reflecting an easy supply of liquidity for information-insensitive securities. (There is always supply versus demand of everything, including liquidity, and either curve can move.)

Long-term investors should generally avoid securities whose values are boosted by “liquidity” as well. Endowments offer this reason for investing in unmarked, illiquid securities including private equity. Everyone wants to be the next David Swensen. This view is dicier because it still lacks a complete general equilibrium foundation. Who are the buyers of liquidity? Why do they not arrange their affairs so they do not need to buy and sell so much so fast? We put “liquidity traders” in models blithely. OK, they are there, but to pass the look in the mirror test we need to understand them and make sure we are not them.

Many long-term investors are passive, not interested in following details of matters of corporate control. That is especially true of well-diversified investors who hold market index portfolios. There is currently a substantial agency problem, in the question how do large highly diversified mutual and exchange-traded funds vote their shares. It would be natural to see more nonvoting shares. Such shares are treated exactly the same way as voting shares for all cash flows, but do not vote. Such shares should offer the same cash-flow stream at a discount, which is exactly what many long-term investors desire. One would then see a natural specialization in which some investors pay a premium for voting rights, which they value, and mutual or exchange-traded funds along with large passive investors harvest a small premium for abstaining from such activity.

3.7 Institutional finance, Intermediary Asset Pricing, Slow-Moving Capital, Supply, and Demand

Recently, several novel views of financial markets have emerged under the banners “institutional finance” (Brunnermeier, Eisenbach, and Sannikov, 2013), “intermediary asset pricing” (He and Krishnamurthy, 2013) “slow-moving capital,” (Mitchell, Pedersen, and Pulvino, 2007), “supply and demand” (Gabaix and Koijen, 2020; Koijen and Yogo, 2020). When we can sign volume—when we can tell who initiated an order—prices rise when buyers initiate a trade and fall when sellers do so (Evans and Lyons, 2002; However, see Brandt and Kavajecz (2004) for a cautionary note on “price pressure” versus “price discovery.”). Each of these offers novel views of the function and operation of financial markets, opening many expected-return spreads. Since much of what the institutions of institutional finance do is high-frequency “information” trading, the visions are related. However, authors in this literature express price distortions in different economic terms, so it is worth thinking about them separately.

Really the whole debate within asset pricing has shifted from macro-finance versus behavioral finance to macro-finance versus institutional finance. The issue is not irrationality of the average investor, but the force of agency frictions in delegated management. And the institutional-finance debate is only about the dividing line: how frequent, pervasive, and quantitatively important institutional frictions are, and how much time-varying investment opportunities, preferences, outside streams, or even macro and monetary policies account for asset price fluctuations.

I emphasize theoretical interpretations here rather than the huge list of anomalies, consistent with the theme of this section: statistical expected return and covariance estimates are poor inputs to portfolio optimization. Instead we are exploring plausible general equilibrium theories with heterogeneity to guide a portfolio view.

We must be careful, however. In many of these stories, making even conventional alpha and beta appears to be easy. We have to constrain the models to the abject failure of active management to earn conventional alpha. At a minimum that warning means, we should calibrate our view of the models to generate persistent price differences that do not amount to much for one-period expected returns. But such price discounts are exactly what should interest our long-term investor.

In the institutional finance view, markets are dominated by traders who are highly leveraged and have little capital. They try to sell on the way down, but in doing so they create “fire sales,” especially as balance-sheet constraints become closer to binding. (This view requires some reason why a firm nearing bankruptcy becomes more risk averse not less, exploiting the call option inherent in bankruptcy.) They even leave arbitrage opportunities like uncovered interest parity sitting like proverbial $20 bills on sidewalks because they do not have balance-sheet capacity to trade them.

If this view is correct, then our long-run investors, deploying pools of unleveraged long-only capital, ought to be able to improve their investment performance—to buy a larger stream of payoffs at a lower price—by stepping in, directly or through intermediaries. At a minimum large investors such as endowments, pension funds, family offices, sovereign wealth funds, and super-wealthy individuals should do so. They should provide capital to capital-constrained trading activities, persistent arbitrages like covered interest parity, and buy during the fire sales. To “slow-moving capital” (Mitchell, Pedersen, and Pulvino, 2007, see also Duffie, 2010 for an integrative review), institutions should respond by investing in large multi-strategy hedge funds that have the expertise to quickly deploy across markets. The spread of securities lending by long-term investors is a small but practical and successful deployment of these views.

This funding does not take any special new insights, and it should trouble us that it does not happen. If you read the pages of our academic journals, you see empirical anomaly after anomaly and theoretical friction after friction. Based on this reading, you would expect rivers of alpha to flow from Greenwich, if not Wall Street, and from transparent organizations who fund easily identifiable arbitrage strategies not secret-sauce trading, and generate easy-to-measure alpha. Yet the striking difference between the alphas reported in theory and empirical papers and the alphas reported by studies of fund performance remains as true of institutional or intermediary finance as it is of behavioral or other anomalies.

Perhaps the frictions are so deep that nobody can get around them, though that case is hard to make. Perhaps the opportunities are small and fleeting. As one banker remarked a while ago, commenting on the arbitrage opportunity of repo spikes, “sure, it’s a $20 bill on the sidewalk, but it’s in Chicago, once, and it’s not worth flying there to pick it up.” That is a deeper challenge to the friction-finance view for another day: constraints bind in moments of crisis and stress, but inequality constraints do not always bind, and if they do there is a strong force for institutional development to make them unbind. To what extent is institutional finance a theory of rare or even one-time crises, and to what extent is it a theory of every day?

Perhaps, however, the alphas to be so gained are small but persistent, and subject to mark-to-market drawdowns. Then they are not visible in conventional return accounting, but looking at the issue as long-run payoffs would allow long-run investors to see and fund the opportunity.

Nonetheless, there is a deep and robust opportunity that someone should be taking. Whether we call the phenomena time-varying risk aversion (habits), share demand due to trading frenzies, slow moving capital, institutional finance, or something else, there is a robust call for someone to take the other side.

Deeply, the proposition in finance that demand curves are flat, so price equals present value of payoffs, does not stem from arbitrage. It stems from risk-bearing capacity, from the willingness of a pool of investors to take risks that others are temporarily unwilling to take. If someone sells a million dollars of Apple stock, the rest of the market has to collectively over-weight Apple, and thereby take risk. The price goes down a little bit to generate a reward. Since this activity requires risk-bearing it cannot be done by pure arbitrageurs. Big pots of money are there to do it. But by and large they do not.

These views are also not yet fully fleshed out to describe heterogeneity, which is the key to turning an equilibrium insight into a portfolio theory. Model that rely on external liquidity traders, irrational agents, or artificial financial frictions make a sensible shortcut for studying the friction at hand, but they beg the look-in-the-mirror portfolio theory question. That is an important step.

In particular, many institutional finance models specify that only leveraged intermediaries hold assets such as stocks, corporate bonds, or mortgage-backed securities, so that when they sell prices decline. But in reality people can buy stocks, they do buy stocks, and in the intermediary finance world, they would benefit from doing so.

At least this world-view has some clear portfolio advice for long-term investors—do not invest everything through leveraged intermediaries and pay a bit of attention to whether a fire sale/buying opportunity is at hand.

4. Concluding Comments

In sum, I opine that portfolio theory and practice for long-run investors, like all asset pricing, is ripe for important changes. Portfolio theory is perceived as somewhat of a dead end: a 50-year-old model that is so hard to calculate in practice that nobody uses it in the investment world, or a benchmark from which it is easy to accuse even the most sophisticated people and institutions of being behavioral morons.

Finance has changed a lot, however, and the progress opens the door to more fruitful portfolio theory, and also for more fruitful two-way effort to unite theory to practice.

I emphasize two conceptual steps which I believe will help to pave the way for this project: looking directly at prices and payoffs, which are the ultimate object of interest for the long-term investor, and looking at portfolios with a view of the general equilibrium of financial markets and one’s place in it. Both views offer heuristics for avoiding common investment mistakes, such as the average investor theorem. Both views also make a lot of sense of much apparently puzzling portfolio practice, and even apparent fallacies. In this way, they bridge the Cambridge–Chicago approaches to behavior that persistently deviates from economic theory. The explosion in our general equilibrium view of the market since the days of CAPM and ICAPM, and the explosion in our understanding of the facts (see Cochrane, 2017 for a review) have portfolio implications for long-run investors that are not really yet explored.

There is, I admit, a sense that I have arrived at many different questions to which some sort of enhanced value seems to be the is the answer—after hedging outside income, buy a stream of dividends at a low price—along with heuristics to stay the course. But just what constitutes value and who this advice applies to is more subtle than it appears. My different stories—heterogeneous outside income versus avoiding securities caught up in a trading frenzy—isolate different securities, and for different investors.

The need to properly hedge outside income or liability streams looms large, and I think it is something done poorly by our current portfolio theory and practice. That involves thinking about payout policies as much as portfolio policies.

Risk management—describe what the bad states of the world are to you the investor, and make sure your portfolio is not bad at just that time—should be the core of investing, portfolio management, and evaluation, not a small afterthought. If this century has taught us anything, it ought to be that unexpected things will happen, they will be financially painful, and resilience is more important than a few basis points of alpha.

There is also a defense in here of the finance industry and modest fees, if not for what they do now for what they could do in the future. Some of the disdain for active management rings of the advice a colleague gave me back when personal computers were new: why buy a computer from Dell, when you can go down to Fry’s and pick up a motherboard, power supply, hard drive, monitor, and case and put it together yourself for 20% less? Indeed, financial management consists of buying generic ingredients, putting them together in an attractive package, branding, and marketing them. Perhaps we should give over the training of MBAs for asset management jobs to the marketing departments of our business schools. But in all the visions I have outlined so far, constructing the right payoff for a long-run investor, matching it to that investor’s liability stream, then managing the portfolio, is not easy. It demand skill, and is worth paying fees for, if not quite the astounding level of fees many people and institutions pay now. Such fees survive the average investor theorem, as their value comes from better matching products to individual circ*mstances. I long felt some guilt working for an institution that charged a lot of tuition to teach MBAs that the industry to which we sent them was pointless. Now, perhaps, we can send them off with a better answer, and a bit of a business plan.

Why do not more institutions take our portfolio advice? Are there agency frictions or other barriers? I think first of all we must look at ourselves. We have a beautiful theory, but we have not done enough to make it practically useful, or to listen to the concerns of actual investors. The people I have met at endowments, asset management companies, sovereign wealth funds, and hedge funds are really smart. They know portfolio theory inside and out. Many are PhDs or ex-academics after all. They would like dearly, for example, to use betas not buckets for risk analysis and diversification. But they face on a daily basis the fact that Σ1μ simply does not work, that betas are unstable, etc. They understand hedge portfolio logic, but they also know that the underlying statistical models are uncertain. And they have to explain what they are doing to clients in simple understandable terms. Much of what I offer here are first glimpses of how to make theory more useful, and more easily explained. We need to do a better job.

Second, there are as usual legal and regulatory barriers. Endowments are not free to adjust payouts as they wish or to use the endowment as a piggy bank. IRS rules put minimums and maximums on payouts. The terms of many gifts specify payout rates and tie the payout to specific expenditure streams, something that can be changed but would take a century to do.

Third, there surely are agency frictions in many institutional investment contexts. University endowments are supervised by an upper level management that may make contrary promises, but ultimately does hire and fire managers based on relatively short-term (reported) results. The obscurity of endowment performance is a natural result. The immense multilayered fees paid by such institutions are a natural source of agency friction. Endowment investment is often exceptionally opaque. Endowments do not make it easy to know how much is invested where, how many fees were paid, and how results are calculated, even for faculty on oversight committees. Opacity is a symptom of agency conflicts. The incentives of university top management, or those of similar philanthropies, may be likewise distorted. University and nonprofit boards of trustees, are typically wealthy people (alumni) who by selection bias are often lucky investors who think themselves skillful, or the recipients of large fees unlikely to object to the practice. At the bottom of it all, non-profit institutions are insulated from the market for corporate control. If a university or philanthropy (or hospital) is badly run, you cannot buy up the stock, fire the management and clean it up. Yes, there is market discipline in the need to attract donors, students, and government funds. But in a very noncompetitive market these are weak, and a competitive market for corporate control would surely add financial discipline to nonprofit institutions. As in private monopolies and oligopolies, the first reward of a profitable nonprofit is an easy life, an iron rice bowl, and a gravy train. But agency frictions and dysfunctional institutional structures are not carved in stone either.

Doubting that view, many other institutions follow similar practices, including family offices, wealth managers, etc. who do not have similar frictions—just the usual caveat emptor we all face when dealing with technically complex services. That thought leaves me emphasizing the first point—we should do a better job, before pointing too many agency-friction fingers at the world for not doing what we recommend. And perhaps we should evaluate ourselves a bit more by whether anyone takes our advice.

1

Since Mertonian portfolio theory is standard fare in textbooks and PhD classes, I do not offer a detailed review. Cochrane (2007) is the natural reference for me to suggest. Starting p. 39, I write an investor’s objective

V(Wt,yt)=maxE0eρtu(ct)dt.

V is the value function, W wealth, and y a vector of state variables. Asset returns follow

dRt=μ(yt)dt+σ(yt)dztdyt=μy(yt)dt+σy(yt)dzt.

Wealth evolves as

dWt=Wα(dRrdt)+Wrdt+(ec)dt

where α is the portfolio weight on risky assets, r is the risk-free rate, and e is an endowment process. The optimal portfolio weights are

α=VWWVWWΣ1(μr)βdR,dyVWyWVWW

(1)

where VW denotes partial derivatives of the value function, Σ=σσ=covt(dRt,dRt) is the conditional covariance matrix of returns, and βdR,dy=Σ1covt(dRt,dy) are conditional regression coefficients of returns on state variables. The investor holds a mean-variance efficient portfolio, plus a set of hedge portfolios for state-variable risk. The weights depend on the derivatives of the investor’s value function. Campbell (2018) Chapter 9, Duffie (2001) Chapter 9, and Campbell and Viceira (2002) also provide excellent treatments.

2

Campbell (2006) has a good early summary of this burgeoning “household finance” literature. Curcuru et al. (2010) also survey and extend both the theoretical and empirical literature. People hold very different portfolios. Many people hold undiversified portfolios, with either no stock or one stock. Balasubramaniam et al. (2021) is an excellent recent examination of individual portfolio holdings, with review of the current literature. They construct a factor model of portfolio holdings, to usefully characterize the dimensions of portfolio heterogeneity.

3

Berk and Green (2004) offer an insightful theory of the persistence of active management in the face of a 50-year Chicago critique: a manager has alpha, but only for a limited investment. The manager thus attracts funds until fees soak up the alpha, leaving no alpha to investors. This theory also accounts for many apparent puzzles such as the fact that performance attracts new funds. Much work remains to be done in this area, but this essay emphasizes all of the aspects of portfolio selection other than the chase for alpha so I do not include the discussion it otherwise merits.

6

A Fidelity ad that PBS viewers have been subjected to lately is a good example, at https://www.ispot.tv/ad/ZqHs/fidelity-investments-grandparents-song-by-tears-for-fears. The ad features a couple who return to their portfolio adviser because one of them wants to start selling hobby art. Just what change in portfolio strategy is Fidelity going to offer in response to this news? Foerster et al. (2017) show that investment advisers do a good deal of portfolio customization. However, adviser fixed effects and the adviser’s own asset allocation—one might say opinions—explain the majority of portfolio variation, not risk tolerance, age, investment horizon, and financial sophistication of the investor. Even investor fixed effects, which should pick up the many other dimensions of heterogeneity that I have alluded to such as outside income risks, are not as important as adviser fixed effects.

References

Balasubramaniam

V.

,

Campbell

J. Y.

,

Ramadorai

T.

,

Ranish

B.

(

2021

): Who owns what? A factor model for direct stockholding, manuscript. https://dx.doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.3795521.

Barro

R. J.

(

2006

):

Rare disasters and asset markets in the twentieth century

,

The Quarterly Journal of Economics

121

,

823

866

.

Berk

J. B.

,

Green

R. C.

(

2004

):

Mutual fund flows and performance in rational markets

,

Journal of Political Economy

112

,

1269

1295

.

Berk

J. B.

,

van Binsbergen

J. H.

(

2020

): Regulation of charlatans in high-skill professions,manuscript. https://dx.doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.2979134.

Betermier

S.

,

Calvet

L. E.

,

Sodini

P.

(

2017

):

Who are the value and growth investors?

The Journal of Finance

72

,

5

46

.

Brandt

M. W.

,

Kavajecz

K. A.

(

2004

):

Price discovery in the U.S. treasury market: the impact of orderflow and liquidity on the yield curve

,

The Journal of Finance

59

,

2623

2654

.

Brunnermeier

M. K.

,

Eisenbach

T. M.

,

Sannikov

Y.

(

2013

): Macroeconomics with financial frictions: a survey, in:

Acemoglu

D.

,

Arellano

M.

,

Dekel

E.

(eds.),

Advances in Economics and Econometrics, Tenth World Congress of the Econometric Society

, Vol

II

,

Cambridge University Press

,

New York, NY

, pp.

4

94

.

Google Scholar

OpenURL Placeholder Text

Campbell

J. Y.

(

2006

):

Household finance

,

The Journal of Finance

61

,

1553

1604

.

Campbell

J. Y.

(

2018

):

Financial Decisions and Markets: A Course in Asset Pricing

,

Princeton University Press

,

Princeton, NJ

.

Google Scholar

OpenURL Placeholder Text

Campbell

J. Y.

,

Cochrane

J. H.

(

1999

):

By force of habit: a consumption-based explanation of aggregate stock market behavior

,

Journal of Political Economy

107

,

205

251

.

Campbell

J. Y.

,

Polk

C.

,

Vuolteenaho

T.

(

2009

):

Growth or glamour? Fundamentals and systematic risk in stock returns

,

The Review of Financial Studies

23

,

305

344

.

Campbell

J. Y.

,

Shiller

R. J.

(

1988

):

The dividend-price ratio and expectations of future dividends and discount factors

,

The Review of Financial Studies

1

,

195

228

.

Campbell

J. Y.

,

Sigalov

R.

(

2022

):

Portfolio choice with sustainable spending: a model of reaching for yield

,

Journal of Financial Economics 143: 188-206.

Google Scholar

OpenURL Placeholder Text

Campbell

J. Y.

,

Viceira

L. M.

(

2001

):

Who should buy long-term bonds?,

American Economic Review

91

,

99

127

.

Campbell

J. Y.

,

Viceira

L. M.

(

2002

):

Strategic Asset Allocation: Portfolio Choice for Long-Term Investors

,

Oxford University Press

,

Oxford

.

Campbell

J. Y.

,

Vuolteenaho

T.

(

2004

):

Bad beta, good beta

,

The American Economic Review

94

,

1249

1275

.

Cho

T.

,

Polk

C.

(

2020

): Putting the price in asset pricing,manuscript, London School of Economics.

Cochrane

J. H.

(

2003

): Stocks as money: convenience yield and the tech-stock bubble, in:

Kaufman

G. G.

,

Hunter

W. C.

,

Pomerleano

M.

(eds.),

Asset Price Bubbles

,

MIT Press

,

Cambridge MA, pp. 175-204

.

Google Scholar

OpenURL Placeholder Text

Cochrane

J. H.

(

2007

): Portfolio theory,manuscript, Hoover Institution, Stanford University. https://www.johnhcochrane.com/research-all/portfolio-theory.Accessed 31 December 2021.

Cochrane

J. H.

(

2008

):

The dog that did not bark: a defense of return predictability

,

The Review of Financial Studies

21

,

1533

1575

.

Cochrane

J. H.

(

2011

):

Discount rates: American finance association presidential address

,

The Journal of Finance

66

,

1047

1108

.

Cochrane

J. H.

(

2013

): Long-run mean-variance analysis in a diffusion environment,manuscript, Hoover Institution,Stanford University. https://www.johnhcochrane.com/research-all/a-mean-variance-benchmark-for-intertemporal-portfolio-theory. Accessed 31 December 2021.

Cochrane

J. H.

(

2014

):

A mean-variance benchmark for intertemporal portfolio theory

,

The Journal of Finance

69

,

1

49

.

Cochrane

J. H.

(

2015

): A new structure for U. S. federal debt, in:

Wessel

D.

(ed.),

The $13 Trillion Question: Managing the U.S. government’s Debt

,

Brookings Institution Press

,

Washington, DC

, pp.

91

146

.

Google Scholar

OpenURL Placeholder Text

Cochrane

J. H.

(

2017

):

Macro-finance

,

Review of Finance

21

,

945

985

.

Constantinides

G. M.

,

Duffie

D.

(

1996

):

Asset pricing with heterogeneous consumers

,

Journal of Political Economy

104

,

219

240

.

Curcuru

S.

,

Heaton

J.

,

Lucas

D.

,

Moore

D.

(

2010

): Heterogeneity and portfolio choice: theory and evidence, Ch. 6. In:

Aït-Sahalia

Y.

,

Hansen

L. P.

(eds),

Handbook of Financial Econometrics: Tools and Techniques, Handbooks in Finance

, vol.

1

, San Diego:

North-Holland

, pp.

337

382

.

Google Scholar

OpenURL Placeholder Text

Davis

J. L.

(

2001

):

Mutual fund performance and manager style

,

Financial Analysts Journal

57

,

19

27

.

Duffie

D.

(

2001

):

Dynamic Asset Pricing Theory: Third Edition

,

Princeton, NJ

:

Princeton University Press

.

Google Scholar

OpenURL Placeholder Text

Duffie

D.

(

2010

):

Presidential address: asset price dynamics with slow-moving capital

,

The Journal of Finance

65

,

1237

1267

.

Ennis

R. M.

(

2020

):

Institutional investment strategy and manager choice: a critique

,

The Journal of Portfolio Management

46

,

104

117

.

Epstein

L. G.

,

Zin

S. E.

(

1989

):

Substitution, risk aversion, and the temporal behavior of consumption and asset returns: a theoretical framework

,

Econometrica

57

,

937

969

.

Evans

M. D.

,

Lyons

R. K.

(

2002

):

Order flow and exchange rate dynamics

,

Journal of Political Economy

110

,

170

180

.

Fama

E. F.

,

French

K. R.

(

1996

):

Multifactor explanations of asset pricing anomalies

,

The Journal of Finance

51

,

55

84

.

Fama

E. F.

,

French

K. R.

(

2002

):

The equity premium

,

The Journal of Finance

57

,

637

659

.

Fama

E. F.

,

French

K. R.

(

2010

):

Luck versus skill in the cross-section of mutual fund returns

,

The Journal of Finance

65

,

1915

1947

.

Ferson

W.

(

2019

):

Empirical Asset Pricing: Models and Methods

,

The MIT Press

,

Cambridge, MA

.

Google Scholar

OpenURL Placeholder Text

Foerster

S. R.

,

Linnainmaa

J. T.

,

Melzer

B.

,

Previtero

A.

(

2017

):

Retail financial advice: does one size fit all?

The Journal of Finance

72

,

1441

1482

.

Gabaix

X.

,

Koijen

R.

(

2020

): In search of the origins of financial fluctuations: The inelastic markets hypothesis, manuscript. https://ssrn.com/abstract=3686935.

Garleanu

N.

,

Panageas

S.

(

2015

):

Young, old, conservative and bold. The implications of finite lives and heterogeneity for asset pricing

,

Journal of Political Economy

123

,

670

685

.

Garleanu

N.

,

Panageas

S.

(

2019

): Heterogeneity and asset prices: a different approach, NBER Working Paper 26607.

Gilbert

T.

,

Hrdlicka

C.

(

2015

):

Why are university endowments large and risky?

The Review of Financial Studies

28

,

2643

2686

.

Gomes

J.

,

Kogan

L.

,

Zhang

L.

(

2003

):

Equilibrium cross-section of returns

,

Journal of Political Economy

111

,

693

732

.

Gormsen

N. J.

,

Lazarus

E.

(

2021

): Duration-driven returns, .The Journal of Finance, forthcoming.

Goyal

A.

,

Welch

I.

(

2003

):

Predicting the equity premium with dividend ratios

,

Management Science

49

,

639

654

.

Hansen

L. P.

,

Sargent

T. J.

(

2001

):

Robust control and model uncertainty

,

American Economic Review

91

,

60

66

.

He

Z.

,

Krishnamurthy

A.

(

2013

):

Intermediary asset pricing

,

American Economic Review

103

,

732

770

.

Koijen

R. S.

,

Yogo

M.

(

2020

): Exchange rates and asset prices in a global demand system, manuscript. https://ssrn.com/abstract=3383677.

Krishnamurthy

A.

,

Vissing-Jorgensen

A.

(

2012

):

The aggregate demand for treasury debt

,

Journal of Political Economy

120

,

233

267

.

Lamont

O. A.

(

2012

):

Go down fighting: short sellers vs. firms

,

The Review of Asset Pricing Studies

2

,

1

30

.

Lamont

O. A.

,

Thaler

R. H.

(

2003

):

Can the market add and subtract? Mispricing in tech stock carve-outs

,

Journal of Political Economy

111

,

227

266

.

Lettau

M.

,

Ludvigson

S.

,

Steindel

C.

(

2002

):

Monetary policy transmission through the consumption-wealth channel

,

Economic Policy Review

8

,

117

134

.

Google Scholar

OpenURL Placeholder Text

Longstaff

F. A.

(

2004

):

The flight-to-liquidity premium in U.S. treasury bond prices

,

The Journal of Business

77

,

511

526

.

Lucas

R. E.

Jr. (

1978

):

Asset prices in an exchange economy

,

Econometrica

46

,

1429

1445

.

Markowitz

H.

(

1952

):

Portfolio selection

,

The Journal of Finance

7

,

77

91

.

Google Scholar

OpenURL Placeholder Text

Maymin

P. Z.

(

2011

):

Self-imposed limits to arbitrage

,

Journal of Applied Finance

21

,

88

105

.

Google Scholar

OpenURL Placeholder Text

Merton

R. C.

(

1969

):

Lifetime portfolio selection under uncertainty: the continuous-time case

,

The Review of Economics and Statistics

51

,

247

257

.

Mitchell

M.

,

Pedersen

L. H.

,

Pulvino

T.

(

2007

):

Slow moving capital

,

American Economic Review

97

,

215

220

.

Panageas

S.

(

2021

): The implications of heterogeneity and inequality for asset pricing,Foundations and Trends in Finance(In press).

Parker

J. A.

,

Schoar

A.

,

Sun

Y.

(

2020

): Retail financial innovation and stock market dynamics: the case of target date funds, manuscript, MIT and Brandeis University..

Reitz

T.

(

1988

):

The equity risk premium: a solution

,

Journal of Monetary Economics

22

,

117

131

.

Rosenthal

L.

,

Young

C.

(

1990

):

The seemingly anomalous price behavior of Royal Dutch/Shell and Unilever N.V./PLC

,

Journal of Financial Economics

26

,

123

141

.

Santosh

S.

(

2014

): The path of price discovery: trade time vs. clock time, manuscript. https://ssrn.com/abstract=2567486.

Schmidt

L.

(

2016

): Climbing and falling off the ladder: asset pricing implications of labor market event risk, manuscript. https://ssrn.com/abstract=2471342.

Shiller

R. J.

(

1993

):

Macro Markets: Creating Institutions for Managing Society’s Largest Economic Risks

,

Oxford University Press

,

Oxford

.

Google Scholar

OpenURL Placeholder Text

Shiller

R. J.

(

2014

):

Speculative asset prices

,

American Economic Review

104

,

1486

1517

.

Stafford

E.

(

2017

): Replicating private equity with value investing, homemade leverage, and hold-to-maturity accounting, manuscript. https://ssrn.com/abstract=2720479.

Wachter

J. A.

(

2003

):

Risk aversion and allocation to long-term bonds

,

Journal of Economic Theory

112

,

325

333

.

Author notes

*

This article is based on a keynote talk prepared for the NBER conference, https://www.johnhcochrane.com, “New Developments in Long-Term Asset Management Spring 2021.” I thank John Campbell, Alex Edmans, Gene Fama, Jim Poterba, Luis Viceira, and a referee for helpful comments.

© The Author(s) 2021. Published by Oxford University Press on behalf of the European Finance Association. All rights reserved. For permissions, please email: journals.permissions@oup.com

This article is published and distributed under the terms of the Oxford University Press, Standard Journals Publication Model (https://academic.oup.com/journals/pages/open_access/funder_policies/chorus/standard_publication_model)

Portfolios for Long-Term Investors* (2024)

FAQs

What is a long-term investment portfolio? ›

Not an asset class but rather a perspective, long-term investments involve taking more risk in the short-term to realize long-term returns by buying and holding diversified securities for years.

What are long-term investments? ›

Long-term investments are assets that an individual or company intends to hold for a period of more than three years. Instruments facilitating long-term investments include stocks, real estate, cash, etc. Long-term investors take on a substantial degree of risk in pursuit of higher returns.

What do long-term investors look for? ›

One way to determine whether a stock is a good long-term buy is to evaluate its past earnings and future earnings projections. If the company has a consistent history of rising earnings over a period of many years, it could be a good long-term buy.

Which is best for long-term investment? ›

13 Best Long-Term Investment Plans for Higher Returns
  • Gold. While gold does not offer monthly dividends, what it does help you do is preserve your wealth. ...
  • Public Provident Funds (PPFs) ...
  • Mutual funds. ...
  • Stocks. ...
  • Fixed deposits.

What should a long-term investment portfolio look like? ›

A good way to minimize risk is by creating a diversified and balanced portfolio with stocks, bonds, and cash that aligns with your short- and long-term goals. From there, you can broaden your portfolio to include other assets like real estate or high-risk investments for an increased likelihood of higher returns.

Does long term investing really work? ›

Long-term stock investments tend to outperform shorter-term trades by investors attempting to time the market. Emotional trading tends to hamper investor returns. The S&P 500 posted positive returns for investors over most 20-year time periods.

What is an example of a long term fund? ›

Long-term finance can be defined as any financial instrument with maturity exceeding one year (such as bank loans, bonds, leasing and other forms of debt finance), and public and private equity instruments.

What is the safest investment with the highest return? ›

Here are the best low-risk investments in April 2024:
  • High-yield savings accounts.
  • Money market funds.
  • Short-term certificates of deposit.
  • Series I savings bonds.
  • Treasury bills, notes, bonds and TIPS.
  • Corporate bonds.
  • Dividend-paying stocks.
  • Preferred stocks.
Apr 1, 2024

How to invest smartly for long-term financial growth? ›

Start by taking stock of your assets and debts, setting up a reasonable debt management plan and understanding how much you need to fully stock an emergency fund. Tackling these financial tasks first ensures that you'll be able to put funds into long-term investments and not need to pull money out again for a while.

How long is considered a long-term investment? ›

Generally, any asset you hold for over five years is considered a long-term investment and you usually distribute your money across a range of assets to build a diversified investment portfolio.

How to plan long-term investments? ›

Five principles for a long-term investment strategy
  1. Match your investments to your goals. ...
  2. Spread your 'eggs' among multiple baskets. ...
  3. Don't try timing the market. ...
  4. Set up a purchase plan–and stick with it. ...
  5. Keep tabs on your progress.

Can you live off an investment portfolio? ›

Once you have $1 million in assets, you can look seriously at living entirely off the returns of a portfolio. After all, the S&P 500 alone averages 10% returns per year. Setting aside taxes and down-year investment portfolio management, a $1 million index fund could provide $100,000 annually.

Which portfolio is best for investment? ›

An aggressive portfolio is ideal for someone with high risk tolerance and a lot of time to invest, while a conservative portfolio is better for someone with low risk tolerance and a short amount of time. A model portfolio doesn't necessarily make it the right portfolio for you.

What is the best bond to invest in? ›

Our picks at a glance
RankFundNet expense ratio
1Vanguard High-Yield Corporate Fund Investor Shares (VWEHX)0.23%
2T. Rowe Price High Yield Fund (PRHYX)0.70%
3PGIM High Yield Fund Class A (PBHAX)0.75%
4Fidelity Capital & Income Fund (fa*gIX)0.93%
5 more rows
Mar 15, 2024

Is 5 years considered a long term investment? ›

Generally, any asset you hold for over five years is considered a long-term investment and you usually distribute your money across a range of assets to build a diversified investment portfolio.

Is 5 years considered long term investing? ›

Know Your Time Horizon

No matter what the goal, the key to all long-term investing is understanding your time horizon, or how many years before you need the money. Typically, long-term investing means five years or more, but there's no firm definition.

How many years is considered a long-term investment? ›

Generally speaking, long-term investing for individuals is often thought to be in the range of at least seven to 10 years of holding time, although there is no absolute rule.

How many years is considered long term? ›

How long are short- medium- and long term? There are no exact definitions, but short-term usually means a period shorter than two years, medium-term covers a range from 2 to 5 or 10 years and long-term is a period longer than 5 or 10 years.

Top Articles
Latest Posts
Article information

Author: Rev. Leonie Wyman

Last Updated:

Views: 6699

Rating: 4.9 / 5 (59 voted)

Reviews: 90% of readers found this page helpful

Author information

Name: Rev. Leonie Wyman

Birthday: 1993-07-01

Address: Suite 763 6272 Lang Bypass, New Xochitlport, VT 72704-3308

Phone: +22014484519944

Job: Banking Officer

Hobby: Sailing, Gaming, Basketball, Calligraphy, Mycology, Astronomy, Juggling

Introduction: My name is Rev. Leonie Wyman, I am a colorful, tasty, splendid, fair, witty, gorgeous, splendid person who loves writing and wants to share my knowledge and understanding with you.